28.06.2013 Views

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

terminology, Leibniz holds that natural right and justice cannot be based on what is<br />

purely possible to do, but must be based on what is right and morally necessary to do.<br />

Therefore (to answer the Euthyphro problem) “goodness and justice have their grounds<br />

independent of will and of force” (RM 46). 51<br />

In the Monita we got a fairly clear idea of the source of these grounds,<br />

independent of will and force; namely, the ideas of right in the divine understanding. In<br />

the Meditation, Leibniz solves the problem of voluntarism in a similar way, by<br />

developing several distinct notions of right and justice. He begins by calling for a “formal<br />

reason” (raison formelle) of justice. This formal reason cannot be power, since, in<br />

addition to the reasons so far given, “if power were the formal reason of justice, all<br />

powerful persons would be just, each in proportion to his power; which is contrary to<br />

experience” (RM 48). What is needed is a formal reason or common notion of justice that<br />

is universally valid for God and humans alike.<br />

It is thus a question of finding this formal reason, that is to say, the why of this<br />

attribute, or this [notion] which should teach us what justice is, and what men<br />

mean in calling an action just or unjust. And this formal reason must be common<br />

to God and to man; otherwise one would be wrong in wanting to attribute, without<br />

equivocation, the same attribute to both: these are fundamental rules of reasoning<br />

and of discourse. (RM 48) 52<br />

Part of Leibniz’s motivation in this passage is to refute certain “dogmas” which deny the<br />

universality of the concept of justice. 53 This formal reason will make the use of power<br />

legitimate and the application of justice consistent. Thus, we must distinguish between<br />

the “necessary and eternal truths which must be the same everywhere” from “that which<br />

is contingent, changeable or arbitrary” (RM 49). To do this, Leibniz devotes perhaps an<br />

inordinate amount of space (including graphics) to show how mathematical patterns, no<br />

matter how complex, remain consistent, certain, and universally agreeable; and, no one<br />

thinks that these patterns hold for God but not for humans (or vice versa). Thus:<br />

The same is true of justice. If it is a fixed term which has some determined<br />

meaning; if, in a word, it is not a simple sound, without sense, like blitiri;<br />

this term, or this word, justice, will have some definition or some<br />

intelligible notion: and from every definition one can draw certain<br />

consequences, by using the incontestable rules of logic; and this is<br />

precisely what one does in building the necessary and demonstrative<br />

sciences which depend not at all on facts, but solely on reason, such as<br />

51 M 42: “… la bonté et la justice ont leurs raisons indépendentes de la volonté et de la force.” In section 4,<br />

we will return to Leibniz’s criticism of Hobbes in relation to the first degree of right (jus strictum).<br />

52 M 45: “Il s’agit donc de trouver cette raison formelle, c’est-à-dire le pourquoi de cet attribut, ou cette<br />

notion qui nous doit apprendre en quoi consiste la justice et ce que les hommes entendent, en appelant une<br />

action juste et injuste. Et il faut que cette raison formelle soit commune à Dieu et à l’homme. Autrement on<br />

aurait tort de vouloir attribuer sans équivoque le même attribut à l’un et à l’autre. Ce sont là les reegles<br />

fondamentales du raisonnement et du discours.”<br />

53 In the Theodicy (sec. 173-177) Leibniz argues against the dogmas that “(1) the nature of justice is<br />

arbitrary, (2) that it is fixed, but it is not certain God will observe it, (3) that the justice we know is not the<br />

justice he observes.” But these are refuted if justice has a “common notion.”<br />

217

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!