28.06.2013 Views

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

action are grounded in the subject, in the moral quality of the acting person. 42 This is well<br />

supported by §14a, as we saw, which says that morality (the justice or injustice of the<br />

action of the person) “springs from the quality of the person.” 43 Now, this term “quality”<br />

is essential, since it refers to the doctrine of the “moral qualities” inherent in persons, i.e.,<br />

rational agents (about which I will say more, below). Also essential is to notice the<br />

complex character of the moral quality. As Leibniz says, the real quality of an action is<br />

two-fold (duplex), since it stems from (1) the moral power to act (jus) and the moral<br />

necessity to act (obligatio). Therefore, ‘right and obligation’ denote the moral quality, or<br />

the subjective power enabling one to perform ‘what is just’ in the objective sense. In<br />

short, the moral qualities designate the subjective sphere of jurisprudence, the qualities of<br />

a person enabling her to act justly.<br />

The passage (§14a) can be generally understood, then, as an expression of the<br />

historical notion of “subjective right,” according to which right is the power of a person<br />

to do what is licit or permissive. Leibniz is certainly influenced in this regard by Grotius’<br />

definitions of ‘right’ in De Jure Belli ac Pacis (1625), as can be seen in what follows. 44<br />

Grotius begins his work by distinguishing several “significations” of ‘right’ (ius). The<br />

first may be called objective right: “For right in this Place signifies merely that which is<br />

just”; and ‘the just’ is what is conducive to “a Society of reasonable creatures” (GR<br />

I.1.3.136). 45 But Grotius then adds:<br />

There is another Signification of the word Right different from this, but<br />

yet arising from it, which relates directly to the Person: In which sense<br />

Right is a moral Quality annexed to the Person, enabling him to have, or<br />

do, something justly. (GR I.1.4.138) 46<br />

42 Leibniz does not emphasize the significance of this identification of morality and justice (nor the<br />

significance of the distinction between justum and justitia); but it is very significant. For example, in the<br />

Elementa, iustitia is clearly defined as a virtue, and comes to play the role that ius plays here, that is, as the<br />

subjective counterpart to the objective iustum. Thus it may be said that ‘subjective right’ implies virtue, for<br />

Leibniz. That justice is a virtue (as it is for Aristotle) has been true from the very beginning. In a brief<br />

passage in De Arte Combinatoria (1666), called “Practica,” Leibniz considers Aristotle’s definition of<br />

justice as a mean of things, and rejects this in favor of justice as a mean in affections: “Justitia (particularis)<br />

est virtus servans mediocritatem circa affectus hominis erga hominem, juvandi et nocendi, seu favorem et<br />

odium. Regula mediocritatis est: licere eo usque alterum (me) juvare, quo usque (alteri) tertio non nocetur .<br />

. . Virtutes quoque non rerum, sed animorum habitus sunt. Quare ostendimus Iustitiam et ipsam in<br />

affectuum moderatione esse positam” (A.6.1.229). Leibniz takes up this definition again in the Elementa,<br />

accepts it again, and then rejects it, as we will see.<br />

43 Again, Leibniz associates justice (justitia) with an act originating in the person, not with the just<br />

condition (iustum).<br />

44 Leibniz in fact mentions and quotes Grotius’s De Jure in numerous places throughout the Nova<br />

Methodus.<br />

45 GJ I.1.3: “Nam ius hic nihil aliud quam quod iustum est significat.” Following that, Grotius actually says,<br />

“Now that is unjust which is repugnant to the Nature of a Society of reasonable Creatures. So Cicero says,<br />

it is unnatural to take from another to enrich one’s self; which he proves thus, because, if every one were to<br />

do so, all Human Society and Intercourse must necessarily be dissolved” (Est autem injustum quod naturae<br />

societatis ratione vtentium repugnat. Sic alteri detrahere sui commodi eansa contra naturam esse dicis<br />

Cicero, idque ita probat, quia si id fiat societas hominum & communitas euertatur necesse fit.)<br />

46 GJ I.1.4: “Ab hac iuris singificatione diversa est altera, sed, ab hac ipsa veniens, quae ad personam<br />

refertur; quo sensu ius est Qualitas moralis personae competens ad aliquid iuste habendum vel agendum.”<br />

12

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!