28.06.2013 Views

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

honorably” (honeste vivere). 124 To live honorably, or with moral rectitude, appears to<br />

mean to live as far as possible according to the wisdom, power, and perfection of God.<br />

The particulars of this degree can be divided into three themes: (A) the role of God’s will<br />

and power (Leibniz’s relation to voluntarism); (B) the coincidence of God’s will with<br />

human utility; and (C) the motives of virtue and of reward and punishment. These themes<br />

are important to Leibniz’s practical philosophy on the whole, so I will discuss each in<br />

turn.<br />

(A) Leibniz begins by characterizing the third degree in a seemingly voluntarist<br />

way: “The third precept of natural right is the will of a superior. And here is what<br />

Thrasymachus was saying to Plato, above: The just is useful to the more powerful.” 125<br />

Does this mean that Leibniz was a voluntarist in the Nova Methodus, as some have<br />

maintained? 126 To address this question correctly, we must note several kinds of<br />

superiority that Leibniz attributes to God in this passage. (1) God is superior by nature.<br />

This refers simply to his natural wisdom, reason, and goodness. On this basis, God is to<br />

be revered. 127 (2) God is superior in law, meaning divine positive law, or revelation,<br />

which is superior to human law. 128 But this does not mean that divine law is superior to<br />

the laws of reason, or even to jurisprudence. As we saw in §4 above, jurisprudence and<br />

natural theology have their common source in reason, and natural theology contains<br />

divine positive law. Moreover, in section §5, natural theology was said to be a species of<br />

jurisprudence. Therefore, divine positive law is a species of jurisprudence and natural<br />

reason. (3) God is superior in regard to contracts, which apparently means that God’s<br />

covenant with man supersedes (is superior to) all other contracts. (4) For these reasons,<br />

“piety is the third degree of natural right, and provides perfection and execution [to the<br />

other two degrees].” 129 This implies that God’s superiority resides in his capacity as<br />

perfect moral judge and upholder of strict right and equity. (5) The most important type<br />

of superiority involves God’s power. God is of course said to be the most powerful being,<br />

and thus has no superior. Furthermore, as can be recalled from § 15, strictly speaking,<br />

“God is the subject of no true obligation.” Therefore, God could violate even strict right.<br />

However, God does not do this, since “because he is omniscient and wise, God confirms<br />

pure Right and equity; and because of his power, it is executed.” 130 This reflects<br />

Leibniz’s life-long intellectualist views, that is, that the ideas of right and good are found<br />

in God’s understanding, rather than determined solely by God’s will. 131 This position also<br />

124 The Latin ‘honestas’ best translates as ‘moral rectitude.’<br />

125 A.6.1.344.§75: “Tertium Juris principium est voluntas Superioris. Et huc quae Trasymachus apud<br />

Platonem supra dicebat: Justum esse potentiori utile.”<br />

126 See Riley (2004) and Welzel (1962, p. 147).<br />

127 A.6.1.344.§75: “Superior autem est vel natura, Deus: Ejusque voluntas iterum est vel naturalis, hinc<br />

Pietas, vel Lex, hinc Jus divinum positivum; vel superior est pacto, ut homo, hinc Jus Civile.”<br />

128 Civil right (jus civile), where the will of the superior holds for humans, is distinguished from divine<br />

right, in the passage directly above.<br />

129 A.6.1.344.§75: “Pietas igitur tertius est gradus Juris Naturae, tribuitque caeteris perfectionem et<br />

effectum.”<br />

130 A.6.1.344.§75: “Nam Deus, quia omniscius et sapiens est, jus merum et aequitatem confirmat; quia<br />

omnipotens, exequitur.”<br />

131 It is appropriate to note Schiedermair’s observation that “Gottes Weisheit ist also hiernach der Ursprung<br />

des Rechtes und sein Wille nur die Exekutive” (p. 62). In Chapter Six, I deal at length with Leibniz’s<br />

criticisms of voluntarism. In Meditation on the Common Notion of Justice and the Monita On the Principles<br />

of Pufendorf, Leibniz claims, against the voluntarist, that justice is founded on the immutable truths of<br />

32

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!