28.06.2013 Views

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

To put it another way: “I complain; you would complain in the same situation; thus I<br />

complain with justice” (RM 55). Let us review the four causes of complaint:<br />

(1) to harm another<br />

(2) to refuse to prevent an evil to another<br />

(3) to refuse to remove an impediment to a positive good for another<br />

(4) to refuse to promote another’s good<br />

These causes of complaint show, by gradual logical increments, not so much that we<br />

would not want X in a certain situation, but that our reasons for wanting X hold up (or do<br />

not hold up) to rational evaluation. This way we understand that refusing to promote<br />

another’s good is a kind of harm to them. Thus the same reasons of complaint persist in<br />

the move from strict right to charity, from the first precept of right to the second.<br />

Beyond having established the causes of complaint, much more is implied in<br />

these passages. What is meant by the species, nature, and thing in the above passage? It<br />

seems plausible to understand the thing as the good for oneself and another—which is to<br />

say justice. We are after all trying to establish “the means for determining the reasons”<br />

for the nominal definition of justice, i.e., “a constant will to act in such a way that no one<br />

have a reason to complain of us.” The reasons for complaint are actually the means for<br />

determining what counts as a just action. One is then supposed to have the virtue (the<br />

constant will) to perform just actions. Furthermore, we can understand that “the nature of<br />

the thing,” justice, is reciprocal reasons. In other words, justice means (at least) the<br />

“constant will” to grant to others the same reasons for action that you would have others<br />

grant to you in the same situation. Thus the Golden Rule, in its positive formulation, is<br />

also implied here. It is furthermore apparent that the species of the thing, justice, are<br />

equality and equity. As we have seen, these terms are associated with the first two<br />

degrees of right, respectively strict right and distributive justice. It is furthermore<br />

tempting to identify equality and equity as the “common notions” that Leibniz has been<br />

alluding to in the Meditation. These implications are brought out by the following<br />

passage, where, in addition, the Golden Rule in its positive form reflects the logic of<br />

complaint.<br />

And it is the principle of equity, or, what is the same thing, of the equality<br />

or of the same reason which holds that one grant [to others] whatever one<br />

would wish in a similar case, without pretending to be privileged against<br />

reason, or [without] being able to allege one’s will as a reason. (RM 56) 67<br />

There are a number of worthy points here. This passage could very well be taken to mean<br />

that the voluntarist’s stat pro ratione voluntas is to be replaced by stat pro voluntate<br />

ratio, which is the “principle of equity” or the Golden Rule. We will come back to this<br />

rule; but first let us focus on the features and meanings of the terms ‘equity’ and<br />

chose.”<br />

67 M 57: “Et c’est le principe de l’equité ou qui est la même chose, de l’egalité ou de la même raison qui<br />

veut qu’on accorde ce qu’on voudrait en pareil cas, sans prétendre d’être privilegié contre la raison ou de<br />

pouvoir alléguer sa volonté pour raison.” Riley’s translation slightly emended.<br />

222

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!