28.06.2013 Views

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

of a set of prudential instructions on how to achieve happiness, or that it is a mere<br />

appendage to the grand scheme of metaphysical perfection. 166 But it seems possible to<br />

understand the matter as precisely the opposite: The ends of metaphysical and moral<br />

perfection depend on the premises established by jurisprudence. We should recall that<br />

theology a species of the genus jurisprudence, universally understood. Is not God’s will<br />

the supreme potentia moralis? To be a moral agent requires not simply the knowledge of<br />

the conditions of metaphysical perfection, or the knowledge of the good for all, but<br />

requires the self-restricting moral power to harmonize one’s ends with the ends of<br />

everyone. This account of right sets Leibniz’s practical philosophy quite part from<br />

accounts that ground it in utilitarian terms. 167 While the agent is indeed obligated to the<br />

good for all, Leibniz is saying that this obligation is grounded in the capacity of the moral<br />

agent, that is, in her right, not in the amount of good that her actions produce. Often<br />

overlooked in these accounts are the normative definitions of right, especially as<br />

established here in the Nova Methodus; and yet they form the core concepts from which<br />

the whole of Leibniz’s practical philosophy can be derived.<br />

It will be important to see, then, which elements of Leibniz’s introductory science<br />

of jurisprudence remain and how they develop. As we turn to his Elementa Juris<br />

Naturalis (1671), we will find one important change taking place. Leibniz will again<br />

attempt a science of jurisprudence (called a science of right) based on definitions; he will<br />

even refine its method in important ways; and the moral qualities will remain central.<br />

However, this time the science will focus considerably on the definition of justice, whose<br />

essence is determined to be love. This change is striking, since nowhere in the Nova<br />

Methodus is love mentioned in relation to jurisprudence. But the themes of love and<br />

justice will become fundamental and permanent elements of Leibniz’s practical<br />

philosophy.<br />

166 As Russell holds, for example, in The Philosophy of Leibniz, p. 197.<br />

167 A good example is René Sève, in his Leibniz et l’ecole modern du droit naturel.<br />

41

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!