28.06.2013 Views

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

our passions and our present concerns as much as [moral doctrine] does,<br />

we would dispute it and transgress it almost as much. (NE 1.2.12.95) 72<br />

Leibniz does not think that the lack of universal use, effectiveness, or agreement on moral<br />

principles is any proof that they are not innate nor universally valid. Interestingly, he says<br />

that nature, not God, as engraved the characters. Likely he is alluding to the natural law<br />

of the Gospel; and whatever it prescribes, it is likely similar to the universal love that is<br />

characteristic of the virtue of justice. Yet we are not given a demonstration of this.<br />

Section 4: Moral doctrine, pure reason, and the science of right<br />

At the beginning of the chapter on innate practical principles, Leibniz agrees with<br />

Locke that moral doctrine is a demonstrable science. What was not established in the<br />

dialogue was any sense of method. However, at the end of the chapter on innate practical<br />

principles, Leibniz provides some methodological pointers about demonstration in<br />

general.<br />

We agree about this; for, far from approving acceptance of doubtful<br />

principles, I want to see an attempt to demonstrate even Euclid’s axioms,<br />

as some of the ancients tried to do. If it be asked how one can know and<br />

investigate innate principles, I reply in conformity with what I have said<br />

above: apart from the instincts the reason for which is unknown, we must<br />

try to reduce them to first principles (i.e. to identical or immediate axioms)<br />

by means of definitions, which are nothing but a distinct setting out of<br />

ideas. (NE 1.2.24-7) 73<br />

Leibniz’s requirements for demonstration are so strict that he even requires, and carries<br />

out elsewhere, demonstrations of Euclid’s axioms. Some of this “distinct setting out of<br />

ideas” we have seen in his analysis of definitions of right, just, and justice. Along these<br />

lines there are several additional positions to examine in the Nouveaux Essais. These<br />

positions do not involve any sensual instincts, but rely solely on the analysis of ideas, and<br />

suggest ways that moral doctrine might still be considered demonstrative. Although no<br />

demonstrations are carried out, these ideas show that some principle of right,<br />

jurisprudence, or even “pure reason” lies at the foundation of morals. Once again we<br />

begin with Locke.<br />

72 NE 1.2.12: “Cette violation supposée, il s’ensuit seulement qu’on n’a pas bien lû ces characteres de la<br />

nature gravés dans nos ames, mais quelques fois assez enveloppés par nos desordres. Outre que pour voir la<br />

necessité des devoirs d’une maniere invincible, il en faut envisager la demonstration, ce qui n’est pas fort<br />

ordinaire. Si la Geometrie s’opposoit autant à nos passions et à nos interests présens que la morale, nous ne<br />

la contesterions et ne la violerions gueres moins...”<br />

73 NE 1.2.24-7: “Nous sommes d’accord sur ce point, car bien loin que j’approuve qu’on se fasse des<br />

principes douteux, je voudrois moi qu’on cherchât jusqu’à la démonstration des Axiomes d’Euclide . . . Et<br />

lors qu’on demande le moyen de connoitre et d’examiner les principes innés, je réponds, suivant ce que j’ay<br />

dit ci dessus, qu’excepté les instincts dont la raison est inconnue, il faut tâcher de les reduire aux premiers<br />

principes, c’est à dire, aux Axiomes identiques ou immediats par le moyen des definitions, qui ne sont autre<br />

chose qu’une exposition distincte des idées.”<br />

193

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!