28.06.2013 Views

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

degrees is to be found in the source of the whole argument of the Codex—in the<br />

definition of right. After all, this was the source in the Nova Methodus. But this source is<br />

repeatedly overlooked.<br />

Let us pick up from where we left off and see what to make of the three degrees. The<br />

account of them in the Codex offers some useful details, although not without some<br />

complications, especially in the third degree.<br />

The precept of mere or strict right is that no one is to be injured, [lest] that<br />

one be given a legal claim within the state, or outside the state a right of<br />

war. From this arises the justice which philosophers call commutative, and<br />

the right which Grotius calls faculty.[ 98 ] The higher degree I call Equity or,<br />

if you prefer, charity (that is, in the narrower sense), and this I extend<br />

beyond the rigor of strict right to [include] those obligations which give to<br />

those whom they affect no ground for [legal] action in compelling us to<br />

fulfill them, such as gratitude and alms-giving, to which, as Grotius says,<br />

we have a moral claim [aptitudo], not a legal claim [facultas]. 99<br />

In this account of the three precepts of right, Leibniz includes the Grotian categories of<br />

faculty and aptitude, marking also the distinction made by Pufendorf between perfect and<br />

imperfect rights. Thus the first degree has the faculty to authorize a legal claim, whereas<br />

the second degree has only a “moral aptitude.” This basically means that beneficence<br />

cannot be legislated, although it can be morally required. Leibniz does not explain here<br />

how something like alms-giving may be morally required, but we can recall some of his<br />

earlier definitions of the just and unjust: the just consists in a proportional distribution of<br />

good, the unjust in taking more than one needs for oneself, and so forth. While almsgiving,<br />

for example, cannot be made law, a sort of moral pressure may be applied when<br />

there is an imbalance. And while benevolence cannot be legislated, the state can do much<br />

to promote the common good; indeed, aside from providing security, establishing laws<br />

that promote the common good is its main function.<br />

Somewhat unclear however is an implication in the first sentence. Does Leibniz mean<br />

that we should not harm another so that the other will not be able to make a legal claim<br />

(or the right of war) against us? It seems it could be taken that way. As we have already<br />

seen, several commentators do think that strict right involves a purely egoistic motive. 100<br />

Leibniz himself has shown that fear of punishment is an effective motive. However, we<br />

should be careful not to confuse motive with ground. Strict right is distinguished from<br />

benevolence as the difference between faculty and aptitude, not as a difference in<br />

motives. We can expect that if egoistic motives were essential to the three degrees that<br />

they would be offered here. But the true ground of strict right lies in the kinds of beings<br />

that we are: beings endowed with the power and freedom to do and not to do that which<br />

98 Riley has “a legal claim.”<br />

99 A.4.5.62: “Juris meri sive stricti praeceptum est, neminem laedendum esse, ne detur ei in civitate actio,<br />

extra civitatem jus belli. Hinc nascitur justitia, quam Philosophi vocant commutativam, et jus quod Grotius<br />

appellat facultatem. Superiorem gradum voco Aequitatem, vel si mavis caritatem (angustiore scilicet sensu)<br />

quam ultra rigorem juris meri, ad eas quoque obligationes porrigo, ex quibus actio iis, quorum interest non<br />

datur, qua nos cogant; veluti ad gratitudinem, ad Eleemosynam; ad quae Aptitudinem, non facultatem<br />

habere Grotio dicuntur.”<br />

100 Hostler (p. 56), Rutherford (p. 55), and Brown (Cambridge Companion p. 421).<br />

133

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!