28.06.2013 Views

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Nevertheless, the application of the modes to specific actions remains unclear. Therefore,<br />

I have devised the following brief examples which I think accurately represent his<br />

intentions.<br />

1. It is just, permitted, morally possible—that I pick an apple from a tree,<br />

provided this tree belongs to no one (i.e., without violating the same right of another<br />

person). This is permitted by ius (the moral quality or faculty enabling me to do preserve<br />

myself as far as is permitted). Since I can refrain from picking the apple as well, this right<br />

is a possible action. It is not morally, logically, nor physically necessary that I pick the<br />

apple. Moreover, another person does not have the moral possibility to take it from me<br />

(once I have acquired it under permissible conditions), although she may have the<br />

physical possibility of doing so.<br />

2. It is unjust, forbidden, morally impossible—that I take an apple against the will<br />

of the one to which the apple belongs, though it is logically and physically possible that I<br />

do so.<br />

3. It is equitable, obligatory, morally necessary—that I do what is equitable; that<br />

is, if I have apples to spare and others need them for their livelihood, or even enjoyment,<br />

then I am morally obligated to distribute them. To refuse another the means of livelihood<br />

when I can provide it without harm to myself constitutes a harm, and even worse, a harm<br />

from which I unnecessarily benefit. However, I am not logically or physically<br />

necessitated to provide for another.<br />

4. It is omissible—that I do nothing with the apples, whether they are mine or not,<br />

and to allow others to take them as they want, as long as it is permitted, and as long as it<br />

is not obligatory. The omissible mode applies to actions having no moral consequence.<br />

These and other relations can be read off the square of inference. But the relations<br />

can be reduced to two main classifications of action: morally possible (encompassing the<br />

just, the obligatory, and the omissible) and the morally impossible (the unjust, forbidden).<br />

This means that most actions fall under the modal category of the possible. As Busche<br />

points out, this means that for Leibniz obligation starts from the “primacy of the<br />

possible,” rather than from the forbidden (or prohibited). I think there is another way to<br />

put it, that obligation starts with the freedom of the subject. The moral quality of a person<br />

is, after all, the power, capability, and virtue to act in a manner consistent with the moral<br />

qualities of another. This implies that a person is capable of transgressing, or acting<br />

inconsistently with, the moral power of another. Thus we can speak of moral freedom, as<br />

consisting in the capacity to limit one’s freedom. Moral possibility implies obligation—<br />

that is, the self-limitation of one’s conduct. Thus, “the primacy of the possible,” morally<br />

speaking, must include a limitation on what is logically possible to do. To conclude from<br />

this so far: Right is the moral power of the good person. Obligation is the moral necessity<br />

of the good person. From these deontic terms one can derive all other relations of deontic<br />

possibility and necessity for the good person.<br />

We must now ask the following: (1) If ‘if p is an obligation -> p is possible’ is<br />

true for Leibniz, what makes p an obligation? To answer this question, we must first<br />

understand that there is an important interrelationship between the modes of right and the<br />

alethic modes. This relationship involves the principle that “ought implies can,” whose<br />

symbolic expression is: Op -> ◊p. This says that if p is obligatory, then p is possible. In<br />

other words, everything obligatory is possible for any rational person to do. That is, you<br />

cannot be obligated to do something that is impossible for you to do. Leibniz<br />

84

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!