28.06.2013 Views

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

however ‘public utility’ is defined. With this in mind we can now turn to the following<br />

sections, wherein the subjective sphere of jurisprudence is defined, as having its source in<br />

the moral agent.<br />

The following sections of the Nova Methodus (§§ 14a-19) are extremely<br />

important, since without them, Leibniz’s practical philosophy cannot be properly<br />

understood. They are also the least well-known, and require close scrutiny and additional<br />

context, since Leibniz provides only a sketch of what their main terms mean. After<br />

having defined jurisprudence as the science of just and unjust actions, in view of their<br />

utility, Leibniz now defines the morality of an act in terms of the “moral quality” of a<br />

person.<br />

The morality, however, that is, the Justice or Injustice of the act of the<br />

person, springs from the quality of the person in view of the order of the<br />

action, stemming from preceding actions, and is called moral Quality.<br />

Since, however, the real quality in the order of the action is two-fold,<br />

namely, the power to act, and the necessity to act; therefore, moral power<br />

is called Right, and moral necessity is called Obligation. 40<br />

This is a striking yet puzzling passage, especially since Leibniz does not provide any<br />

immediate explanation for it. In what follows I will try to fill in the relevant contextual<br />

background, focusing on the terms moral quality, right, and obligation. Let us begin by<br />

rephrasing the passage more simply: The morality (or the justice) of the act of a person<br />

originates in the moral quality of the person. The moral quality has a two-fold character:<br />

Right, which is the power to act; and Obligation, which is the necessity to act. Thus the<br />

morality of the act of a person is grounded in the moral qualities of right and obligation,<br />

which are the qualities of a person acting. One of the most important questions here is<br />

wherein lies the “necessity” to act.<br />

Now, let us understand that by comparing jurisprudence with morality (as in §14<br />

and §14a, respectively), Leibniz is not making a distinction between legality and<br />

morality. 41 Rather (like Grotius) he is distinguishing the objective sphere of jurisprudence<br />

from its subjective sphere. In §14, jurisprudence is defined as the science of just and<br />

unjust actions. By “just and unjust actions,” he means actions in relation to an objective<br />

order of things, i.e., those actions that are objectively just, namely, actions that promote<br />

public utility. By contrast, §14a defines a subjective sphere of jurisprudence, i.e.,<br />

morality. The morality of an action is identified not with the just (justum), but with<br />

justice (justitia). This means, among other things, that the morality and justice of an<br />

40 A.6.1.301.§14[a]: “Moralitas autem, seu Justitia, vel Injustitia actionis oritur, ex qualitate personae<br />

agentis in ordine ad actionem, ex actionibus praecedentibus orta, quae dicitur: Qualitas moralis. Ut autem<br />

Qualitas realis in ordine ad actionem duplex est: Potentia agendi, et necessitas agendi; ita potentia moralis<br />

dicitur Jus, necessitas moralis dicitur Obligatio.” In a late revision, Leibniz strikes out “ex actionibus<br />

praecedentibus orta.” Also important is this late revision note: “Potentia et necessitas, id est posse et non<br />

posse non.” This indicates that Leibniz understood potentia also as a moral possibility. This is important<br />

since in the Elementa Juris Naturalis Leibniz clearly associates the just (iustum) with what is possible for a<br />

good person (vir bonus). “Iustum est qvicqvid possibile est fieri à Viro Bono” (A.6.1.480). This will be<br />

discussed at length in Chapter Two.<br />

41 See Schneiders (1966) p. 609.<br />

11

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!