28.06.2013 Views

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

This formulation of justice as a virtue involving affects serves to move Leibniz<br />

toward considering what sort of virtue justice really is, and what exactly a just condition<br />

is. These are important developments toward deciding whether justice involves a mean in<br />

things or in a mean of affections. As we turn to Draft 3, Leibniz again endorses a view he<br />

had originally broached in the very last paragraph of his De Arte Combinatoria (1666). 31<br />

There, he had cited Grotius’ criticism of Aristotle, 32 according to which, Aristotle had<br />

miscategorized the kind of virtue that justice is. Virtues generally are means of affections.<br />

But Aristotle classifies justice as a mean in things, meaning that justice is the disposition<br />

to give another her due in things or goods. According to Grotius, this is a<br />

misclassification of species (or a category mistake) since, if virtues are means of<br />

affections, and justice is a virtue, justice cannot consist in a mean of things. Leibniz,<br />

however, claims that justice can be understood as a mean of affections, although in the<br />

De Arte Combinatoria he does not explain how. But in the Elementa he does, and<br />

moreover he hits upon the theme that will become a central and permanent component of<br />

subsequent definitions of justice.<br />

Aristotle has arranged all the virtues in a certain moderating affection,<br />

with the sole exception of justice, which is concerned with a medium of<br />

things. But if you will have examined [the matter] more closely, you will<br />

learn that justice is the moderator of love and aversion of a man toward<br />

other men. Nor indeed must we love one so that we harm another; nor hate<br />

one more than required of another. Now there are two rules for moderating<br />

these affections: 1. Harm no one. 2. Help everyone, so far as not to harm a<br />

third. In the former rule Justice is founded; in the latter is Friendship or<br />

Equity. 33<br />

Presumably, Leibniz thinks that the right kind of affection toward others will result in the<br />

right kind of action. However, he also seems to think of these “two rules” he cites here as<br />

regulating the affections. This is an important point. Notably, these two rules correspond<br />

to the first two degrees of natural right, i.e., strict right and equity. He also goes on to say<br />

that only the first rule may be enforced or regulated, while the rule of helping<br />

(characteristic of friendship) may not be. 34 This is quite sensible, since it does not seem<br />

possible legally to enforce affections. At the same time, affections require some kind of<br />

rule, and Leibniz will be forever seeking the right rule for them. But the most significant<br />

development in this passage is the implicit introduction of the notion of practical love.<br />

31<br />

A.6.1.229-30. Also, I cite most of this passage in Chapter One, on discussion of §14 of the Nova<br />

Methodus.<br />

32<br />

GJ prolegomena sec. 44-45. Virtue as a mean in affections is discussed by Aristotle in AE 1106a15-<br />

1106b. Justice as a mean of things may be seen, roughly, at 1133b33. I do not address whether Grotius or<br />

Leibniz’s understanding of Aristotle is accurate. Busche remarks that Leibniz’s claims are hard to verify<br />

from Aristotle’s text (B 460, fn. 119).<br />

33<br />

A.6.1.455: “Aristoteles collocavit virtutes omnes in affectu qvodam moderando, solius justitiae medium<br />

in rebus tantum qvaesivit. At si acutius introspexeris, comperies justitiam esse moderatricem amoris atqve<br />

odii hominis erga hominem. Neqve enim unum ita amare debemus, ut alteri noceamus; neqve unum ultra<br />

odisse, qvam alteri opus est. Duae sunt autem Regulae Affectus huius moderandi, I.) neminem laedere, 2.)<br />

cuiqve qvousqve alius non laeditur prodesse. In illo Iustitia fundatur, in hoc Amicitia seu Aeqvitas.”<br />

34<br />

A.6.1.455: “Licet autem impedire laedentum, non me tantum, sed alium. Ad juvandum alios cogi non<br />

possum, regulariter.”<br />

52

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!