28.06.2013 Views

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

egulating our practice. (E 1.2.3)<br />

In sum, in only one sense is there an innate practical principle, for Locke, i.e., a natural<br />

inclination to pursue pleasure and avoid pain. As he says in a later chapter, “things then<br />

are good or evil, only in reference to pleasure or pain. That we call good, which is apt to<br />

cause or increase pleasure, or diminish pain in us. . . we name that evil which is apt to<br />

produce or increase pain” (E.2.20.2). As we will see, Leibniz agrees with Locke that we<br />

are motivated by pleasure and pain and that these are innate principles. However, he will<br />

also claim that this principle is not sufficient for morally correct action. Thus, there are<br />

principles of reason that, when not obscured by custom, passions, and habits, not only<br />

move us to act, but move us to act rightly.<br />

Section 3: Leibniz on innate practical principles<br />

One interesting feature of Leibniz’s engagement with Locke over innate<br />

principles is that from the beginning Leibniz takes his most fundamental metaphysical<br />

assumption out of play.<br />

I believe indeed that all thoughts and actions of our soul come from its<br />

own depths and could not be given to it by the senses [as you are going to<br />

see in the following]. But in the meantime I shall set aside the inquiry into<br />

that, and shall conform to accepted ways of speaking, since they are<br />

indeed sound and justifiable, and the outer senses can be said to be, in a<br />

certain sense, partial causes of our thoughts. (NE 1.1.1.74) 19<br />

In strict metaphysical rigor, for Leibniz, all determinations of a substance are intrinsic to<br />

that substance. Thus, there would be no point in distinguishing innate ideas from acquired<br />

ones, since whatever a substance will know or experience is already contained within the<br />

substance. All acquired knowledge is thus considered clear and distinct knowledge of<br />

what was formerly confused and obscure. Nevertheless, Leibniz maintains it makes sense<br />

to speak on the empiricist level about knowledge acquired from experience and the<br />

senses. In this way, he can say that while we may not be consciously aware of innate<br />

speculative principles, such as the principles of identity and contradiction, we can<br />

nevertheless come to recognize them through experience, reflection, and demonstration.<br />

Leibniz can also distinguish truths of fact drawn from sense experience from truths of<br />

reason derived only from the innate understanding.<br />

But it seems that the author’s [Locke’s] zeal, highly praiseworthy as it is,<br />

has carried him too far in another direction. In my opinion he has not<br />

adequately distinguished the origin of necessary truths, whose source is in<br />

the understanding, from that of truths of fact, which are drawn from sense<br />

19 A.6.6.74: “Je crois meme que toutes les pensées et actions de notre ame viennent de son propre fonds,<br />

sans lui pouvoir être données par les sens, comme vous allées voir dans la suite. Mais à present je metrai<br />

cette recherce à part, et m’accommodant aux expressions receuës, puis qu’en effet elles sont bonnes et<br />

soutenables, et qu’on peut dire dans un certain sens, que les sense externes sont causes en partie de nos<br />

pensées.”<br />

173

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!