28.06.2013 Views

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

of right. Since right is the moral power to do what is just, obligation follows as the moral<br />

necessity to do what is just. But the argument from love introduces a difficulty: If to love<br />

is just (equitable), and to love is to find pleasure in the good of another, then we are<br />

obligated to find pleasure in the good of another. In fact, love makes it motivationally<br />

possible to be just, so therefore we are obligated to love another. Yet consequently if we<br />

do not find pleasure in the good of another, then we cannot act justly; and arguably we<br />

ought to act justly, whether or not we find pleasure in it. In addition, it seems strange to<br />

make feelings obligations, since feelings are experiences we either have or do not, as the<br />

result of doing certain things and cannot be commanded. However, I think that Leibniz<br />

actually thinks that a feeling, namely, the pleasure in love, can be obligated in the<br />

following way: We are obligated (by right) to be equitable. To be equitable is to love<br />

everyone. In order to act equitably, we must find pleasure in it. Therefore, if we do not<br />

find pleasure in equity, then we are obligated to find pleasure in it. Feelings may not be<br />

commanded right away, but we can develop the habit of having the appropriate feeling in<br />

order to perform our obligations. That is, if we do not already possess the virtue or<br />

disposition to act justly, then we are obligated to acquire it. We are obligated because<br />

acting equitably is required by right. This is in fact why justice turns out to be the virtue<br />

of acting justly. This way of understanding the matter of obligation makes sense. Since<br />

the just means to love everyone, then justice means “the habit of loving everyone.” In<br />

fact, exactly this definition of justice introduces the following Drafts, 5 and 6, and<br />

generates a substantial demonstration, as we will soon see.<br />

Finally, the last sentence of the paragraph and of Draft 4: “Right (ius) is the power<br />

(potentia) of doing what is just (iustum)”. This concluding sentence seems to come out of<br />

nowhere, unless we recall that the term right was investigated in the very first paragraph<br />

of the investigation. There we found the moral qualities implied: right is a moral power;<br />

obligation a moral necessity. Now we can fit this in with the rest of the investigation.<br />

Right is the power of loving everyone, of doing what is morally permissible, morally<br />

possible, what is just. And since right is a duplex quality, these are our obligations, as<br />

well. 112 This is significant because it means that the just is ultimately grounded in, or<br />

made possible by, subjective right, i.e., the moral qualities of a rational substance. It is<br />

also important to note that the moral qualities of right and obligation will be explicitly reintroduced<br />

in Drafts 5 and 6 as the moral qualities of the vir bonus, and used to develop<br />

an a priori normative “logic of right.”<br />

There is however another level to keep in mind. The whole investigation began on<br />

this premise: “From the beginning, however, both our own good and that of others are<br />

involved in the question of right.” We saw that the definition of love was introduced there<br />

as the descriptive motive that makes it possible to carry out the prescriptive (normative)<br />

demands of right. At least, that is my argument, that Leibniz is working out the<br />

descriptive and prescriptive levels of right, and these levels must be understood to have<br />

separate grounds. It is apparent that the descriptive principles of pleasure and happiness<br />

are invoked largely as psychophysical motives, whose function is to make it possible to<br />

perform what subjective right normatively prescribes. Strictly speaking, if I am obligated<br />

to “love” someone, then it is only because right imposes this obligation. I am not<br />

obligated by the psychophysical motivation. However, the only way I can fulfill the<br />

112 Actually, this is misleading, since it appears to make all permissions obligatory; but all that is meant is<br />

that “everything morally necessary is permissible.” This will be clarified in section 4.<br />

75

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!