28.06.2013 Views

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

constant, I say, not that it may not be changed, but that it may not be changed easily.” 120<br />

A bit further down, ‘the good person’ is defined as ‘one who loves everyone.’ These<br />

definitions show, at least, that Leibniz conceives of justice as a habit or disposition, that<br />

is, as the virtue of loving universally. Thus, the good person is one who possesses the<br />

habit of universal love. This suggests that universal love is a duty. But how far is this<br />

duty supposed to extend? It is the purpose of what follows to try to determine the scope<br />

of obligation. It is also very important to note that an important change in the definition<br />

of the “objective sphere” of jurisprudence has taken place. Recall that in the Nova<br />

Methodus “the just” was defined as “public utility.” From now on however ‘the just’ and<br />

‘justice’ will be defined in terms of love, where ‘love’ means not erotic love (although he<br />

still uses the term amor) but rather universal benevolence or caritas. In other words,<br />

where the just (or objective sphere of right) meant ‘public utility,’ it now means ‘loving<br />

everyone.’ Justice is then the virtue of loving everyone. This shift is also significant since<br />

it represents an important step toward Leibniz’s eventual definition of justice as ‘the<br />

charity of the wise,’ first broached in 1677.<br />

Now that the just condition has been redefined as loving everyone, and justice has<br />

been defined as the virtue of loving everyone; and, the good person is one who loves<br />

everyone, the next step is to redefine the subjective counterpart to these objective<br />

conditions. That is, the moral qualities of the good person are now to be understood as<br />

the virtues of the good person. The moral qualities are introduced in the passage<br />

immediately following the above definitions.<br />

Right is the power<br />

Obligation the necessity<br />

(of the good person, for what Grotius called Moral Qualities,<br />

are nothing other than the qualities of the good person). 121<br />

As we saw in the Nova Methodus, the moral qualities of right and obligation were<br />

qualities of a rational substance. 122 We called these qualities the basis of “subjective<br />

right,” that is, the qualities of a person that enable him/her to act morally and justly. But<br />

now we can understand the moral qualities as virtues. That is, justice is the disposition or<br />

moral power (potentia) of a person to love everyone. It helps to note briefly that the<br />

phrase, ‘the good person’ (vir bonus) was commonly used by Cicero and others to signify<br />

a morally and intellectually distinguished person. 123 Leibniz himself however seems to<br />

have Aristotle’s phronemos, or “man of practical wisdom” in mind. This is affirmed in a<br />

passage a bit further down (in Draft 6), where Leibniz directly refers to Aristotle’s Ethics.<br />

Wisely the Roman Jurisconsults, when the laws could not clearly<br />

determine the case, often depended on the judgment of the good person, in<br />

120 A.6.1.480: “IUSTITIA est habitus (seu status confirmatus) viri boni, confirmatus inqvam, non ut mutari<br />

non possit, sed ut non facile possit.” Worth noting is the similarity of Leibniz’s second definition to<br />

Ulpian’s definition in the Digest 1.1.10: “Iustitia est constans et perpetua voluntas ius suum cuique<br />

tribuendi.”<br />

121 A.6.1.465: “Ius est potentia: Obligatio necessitas: viri boni, qvas Grotius vocat Qvalitates Morales, nihil<br />

sunt aliud qvam qvalitates viri boni.”<br />

122 See §14 and §15 of N.M.<br />

123 According to Busche, (p. 473 fn 169).<br />

79

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!