28.06.2013 Views

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

what conforms to the best or perfect in nature, whether that be human nature, or, in the<br />

case of the Stoics, nature in the divine-rational sense, i.e., the logos. Leibniz will maintain<br />

that these views are partly correct, since Aristotle was right about virtue being a natural<br />

human excellence, and since the Stoic logos is simply the natural law of God. At the<br />

same time, for Epicurus the natural law is what is useful to oneself, or “whatever truly<br />

produces pleasure in the soul and tranquility of mind” (A.6.1.342. §71). This too is<br />

agreeable to Leibniz, as long as pleasure does not remain the rule. 86 Leibniz then asserts<br />

as quite sound a principle from Cicero’s De Officiis, that “no one is born for himself, but<br />

is claimed partly by his country, partly his parents, and partly by his friends.” 87 This<br />

seems to express the natural laws of obligation and society we find in Leibniz. Thus, he<br />

agrees with Grotius and Aristotle, against Hobbes, that humans are social by nature<br />

(hominem esse natura socialem). 88 Yet another opinion Leibniz agrees with is that of<br />

Sforza Pallavicino, who held that “the just” is whatever is pleasing to nature, that is,<br />

whatever is beautiful and ordered in the movements of nature. 89 Then, Leibniz again<br />

conveys his understanding of Hobbes. He cites Hobbes’ De Cive Elementa as holding<br />

that the condition of man is either (1) outside of a superior in state of nature, or (2) under<br />

a superior in the civil state. In (1) is the rule of all against all or the right of war; in (2) the<br />

right of nature no longer obtains and the rule becomes “whatever pleases the State.”<br />

Since the state of nature is destructive, everyone is disposed by “sane reason” to pursue<br />

peace in the civil state. 90 Leibniz does not here indicate whether he agrees or disagrees—<br />

perhaps both. As we have seen, Leibniz allows that in a state of nature every person has<br />

the right of war; and that this right is better managed within the State (§17). Thus Leibniz<br />

appears very similar to Hobbes. Yet he seems to differ in two ways: (1) as he has<br />

suggested just above, human social nature tends us toward society, rather than toward a<br />

state of war; 91 (2) although Leibniz holds there is a right of war, it is restricted by<br />

obligation; that is, it is valid only when one’s right is violated. This also implies that the<br />

natural law must not subject us (as Hobbes appears to say) to whatever pleases the State,<br />

especially if this means being subject to abuse by the State. Yet another opinion<br />

mentioned is that of Robert Scharrok, who, like Epicurus, holds that the highest good is<br />

the desire of the heart (or soul). On this view, injustice is due to wrong desires and is<br />

countered by right ones. According to Scharrok, “God has so created our heart that a<br />

86<br />

The role of pleasure for Leibniz is quite important and will be examined in Chapter’s Two, Five, and Six.<br />

Leibniz is much closer to Aristotle and the Stoics. For Aristotle, the “good man” judges rightly what the<br />

true good is in things, whereas “error seems to be due to pleasure, for it appears a good when it is not” (AE<br />

Bk. 3.113b). In addition, the highest good for Aristotle is eudaimonia, not pleasure. For the Stoics, pleasure<br />

is the result of virtue, but not the goal of virtue.<br />

87<br />

Cicero: De officiis, I, 22; De finibus II, 45 (cited by Busche p. 427 fn. 118). In a late revision note (Z. 16-<br />

17) Leibniz adds: “(to which I may have added) God the whole” “(ut ego addiderim) Deus totum.”<br />

88<br />

See De Cive I.2. for Hobbes’ view.<br />

89<br />

Italian Cardinal and Jesuit, b. 1607; d. 1667. Leibniz refers to his book Philosophia moralis seu de Bono<br />

(1646).<br />

90<br />

A.6.1.342.§72: “Th. Hobbes in subtilissimus de Cive Elementis sic procedit: Statum hominum esse vel<br />

extra superiorem, vel sub superiore seu in civitate. Illic esse Jus merum omnium in omnia sed Jus belli, sed<br />

cum status belli sit exitiosus, teneri quemlibet sana ratione duce, ut se disponat ad pacem, statum in una<br />

civitate, quantum in se est, constituta autem civitate simpliciter juris esse quicquid civitati placuit, neque<br />

aliud ibi naturae jus obtinere.”<br />

91<br />

Implying preference to Aristotle’s view of man as a social/political animal, Leibniz cites here John<br />

Felden’s Elementis Jurisprudentiae as having “reduced and refined Aristotle’s principles.”<br />

25

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!