28.06.2013 Views

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Beginning with jus strictum or what he often calls “pure” and “strict right,”<br />

Leibniz shows how the precept “harm no one” follows from the definition of right as a<br />

moral quality:<br />

Strict or pure right descends from the definition of terms, and when rightly<br />

considered, is nothing other than the Right of war and peace. 98<br />

Just as everyone has the right to one’s own body, everyone has the obligation not to<br />

impede another’s right to his or her own body. To say that this means nothing other than<br />

the right to war and peace means this: when you violate another’s right, you invoke her<br />

right of war, or what may be called right to self-defense. The right of peace is simply the<br />

condition in which the right to one’s body is not violated. “For between persons the right<br />

of peace rules so long as one does not instigate a war, or a harm.” 99 The right of peace is<br />

logically prior to the right of war. Therefore, the precept of strict right, harm no one,<br />

“follows” from the definition of terms; namely, from the definitions of right and<br />

obligation as the moral qualities of persons. 100<br />

It is worth remarking again on how Leibniz compares to Hobbes on this point. On<br />

one hand, for Hobbes, the Right of Nature is the right of self-preservation. This is similar<br />

to Leibniz’s strict right. However, for Hobbes the right of nature leads to “a condition of<br />

Warre of every one against every one,” in which “every man has a Right to every thing;<br />

even to one anothers body” (H 1.14). But for Leibniz, no one has a right to another’s<br />

body. One may have the physical capacity, but not the moral right. Furthermore, the state<br />

of nature is not a perpetual state of war among self-interested agents; but is rather<br />

(normally) a state of peaceful coexistence among naturally social beings. We move into<br />

civil society and into the state of justice, not as a prudential matter of self-preservation,<br />

but rather as a natural extension of our natural right of peace. 101 As Leibniz said just<br />

98<br />

A.6.1.343.§73: “Jus strictum seu merum ex terminorum definitione descendit, et est si recte expendas,<br />

nihil aliud quam Jus belli et pacis.” A late revision note to this line is added: “Merum simpliciter in<br />

conservatione pacis consistit, ut ne quid fiat qvo cuiqvam belli ratio praebeatur.”<br />

99<br />

A.6.1.343.§73: “Nam inter personam et personam tamdiu est Jus pacis, quamdiu alter non incepit bellum,<br />

seu laesit.”<br />

100<br />

Although, it ought to be pointed out as a matter of logic that this “following” cannot be a strictly logical<br />

following. Precepts, which are imperatives, and thus not true or false, cannot be logically derived from<br />

definitions, since the latter are propositions true or false. However, though this is just speculation, perhaps<br />

Leibniz does not conceive of the precepts as deriving from propositions. He may conceive of the moral<br />

qualities as containing a command-like character, e.g., do the good; refrain from wrong.<br />

101<br />

On this point Grotius can be distinguished from Hobbes, as well. Citing this sentence from Creech,<br />

“Nature [alone] cannot distinguish iniquity from the just (nec natura potest iusto secernere iniquum),”<br />

Grotius responds that this may be true for animals, but not men: “Now amongst the Things peculiar to Man,<br />

is his Desire of Society, that is, a certain Inclination to live with those of his own Kind, not in any Manner<br />

whatever, but peaceably, and in a Community regulated according to the best of his Understanding; which<br />

disposition the Stoicks termed Oikeiwsin”(GR 81); (Inter haec autem quae homini sunt propria, est<br />

appetitus societatis, id est communitatis, non qualiscunque, sed tranquillae & pro sui intellectus modo<br />

ordinatae, cum his qui sui sunt generis quam oikeiosin Stoici appellabant” (GJ Prolog. 6). According to<br />

Barbeyrac’s footnote to Grotius’ passage, referring to others who have noted the natural sociability, “They<br />

all seem to have copied Aristotle in this Particular, who says, Idoi d an tis, kai en tais planais ws<br />

OIKEION apas antrwpo kai filon. Ethic. Nicom. Lib. VIII. Cap. I.” What Aristotle actually says there<br />

(1155a21) is slightly different: “Idoi d an tis, kai en tais planais ws oikeion apas anqrwpos anqrwpw<br />

kai filon” (“We may see even in our travels how disposed to friendship every man is to every other”).<br />

27

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!