28.06.2013 Views

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

of pain is itself a pleasure). But pleasure is not sought for any other sake. Therefore,<br />

pleasure is a good in itself. 100 Thus, Leibniz’s argument depends on this descriptive<br />

principle: everything is sought for the pleasure it gives. Let us then call this “condition<br />

(C),” or “the pleasure condition,” and add it to the set of conditions, A and B. So then, of<br />

the two cases, servant and friend, only in friendship is the good, i.e., the pleasure of<br />

another, sought for its own sake. In other words, when I seek the pleasure of my friend, it<br />

is not my pleasure I am seeking, but my friend’s; thus, the pleasure is sought for its own<br />

sake. 101<br />

This however solves only part of the problem. It solves only the means-end<br />

condition, (A). An act is just, if and only if the good sought in the act is not done from the<br />

motive of gaining one’s own good. This has been shown to be possible in the case of<br />

friendship or love. But now the ego condition (B), must be met, and this becomes tricky.<br />

Once again, the pleasure condition (C) is asserted, and then the solution.<br />

In the consensus of mankind everything pleasant in itself is sought after in<br />

itself, and everything sought after in itself is pleasant. We can therefore<br />

readily understand how we can not only achieve the good of others<br />

without our own, but can even seek it in itself; namely, in so far as the<br />

good of others is pleasant to us. A true definition of love can be built from<br />

this. For we love him whose good is our delight. (LL 137) 102<br />

Leibniz repeats the definition of love he first introduced in the investigation of right.<br />

Love is taking pleasure, or delight, in the good of another. When the good of others,<br />

which is a good in itself, i.e., pleasure, is pleasant to us, then we get pleasure from love.<br />

When we love we gain pleasure from the other’s pleasure. Thus the ego condition is<br />

fulfilled, and the paradox appears to be resolved. We can act justly, and we have the<br />

required psychological motive to do so.<br />

But this argument should appear rather unconvincing. We are now supposed to<br />

think that when we seek the pleasure of another we are seeking it only for its own sake.<br />

That is condition A. Yet, at the same time, we get pleasure from doing A; thus condition<br />

B is met. But if I get pleasure from A, then how can my act truly be said to be done for its<br />

own sake? It seems the skeptic may still suspect that we love for the sake of the pleasure<br />

we get from love.<br />

I think Leibniz actually has a better explanation here, which is implied in his brief<br />

reference to Stoic honestas. Between the above two passages, Leibniz launches a brief<br />

but bitter attack on the Stoics, those “cloud-dwellers,” and “enemies of reason,” for<br />

100 It is important to note that Leibniz does not say that pleasure is the only good, or that it is the highest<br />

good. In Chapter Six we will see how Leibniz modifies and qualifies these hedonistic claims.<br />

101 Perhaps this example helps to illustrate. Suppose that I urge my friend to become a jurisconsult. Suppose<br />

I think that it is good to become a jurisconsult. Perhaps my friend, or the world, will be better off with more<br />

jurisconsults. But if this is not my friend’s own end, then it is not an end sought for its own sake. True<br />

friendship is when the good sought is pleasure, but for the ends that are the other’s own. This of course may<br />

be a problem, in case the other does not recognize that his own ends are bad.<br />

102 A.6.1.464: “Consensu generis humani omne jucundum per se expetitur et qvicqvid per se expetitur est<br />

jucundum. Ergo facile intelligi potest, qvomodo bonum alienum non nostrum tantum fieri possit, sed et per<br />

se expetatur, qvoties scilicet jucundum est nobis, bene aliis esse. Unde exstruitur vera definitio amoris;<br />

Amamus enim eum, cui bene esse delectatio nostra est.”<br />

70

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!