28.06.2013 Views

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

out of hope or fear, but by a [right propensity 97 ] of his soul, is so far from<br />

not behaving justly that, on the contrary, he acts more justly than all<br />

others, imitating in a certain way, as a man, divine justice. (RP 72) 98<br />

This view also answers the Euthyphro problem in the Meditation: Just as God sees the<br />

good and loves it by its good nature, we love God by virtue of his good nature. We see<br />

that God’s justice stems from his understanding or reason, and so we love him on that<br />

account—not on account of his capacity for rewarding and punishing us. True piety, then,<br />

consists in the love for God that stems from recognizing that God’s goodness is rational,<br />

that is, rational by nature. But human nature has of course something of God’s reason and<br />

moral power—and the ability to imitate it; and the more we imitate God, the more rightly<br />

we act.<br />

It should also be understood that Leibniz is emphasizing the role of God’s will.<br />

God has not only a rational nature, but the will to do what is just. Now, in actuality<br />

Leibniz does not maintain a strict separation between God’s understanding and God’s<br />

will. Rather, God’s understanding provides a kind of inclination for God to do the good.<br />

When God sees the good, he not only recognizes it, but he is inclined to make it a reality.<br />

Since God is perfect his inclination is always in accord with his reason. In this way God<br />

acts spontaneously, completely determined by his own nature. 99 But we who are not<br />

perfect may be inclined in any number of ways (e.g., by weakness of will, passions, bad<br />

customs, the command of a superior, or lack of knowledge of the good). But those who<br />

possess “true piety” will do their best to imitate God’s perfection, by setting their<br />

inclinations in accord with the principles of morals, the precepts of right reason. Leibniz<br />

here provides an account of moral perfection which dispenses with the motives of fear<br />

and punishment, provides rational grounds for actions, and urges the regulation of the<br />

will by means of the development of virtue following these rational grounds.<br />

However, Leibniz is of course well-known for his accounts of pleasure and<br />

happiness, and he does not leave them out here. Therefore, we must consider whether it is<br />

pleasure, rather than “respect for right and equity,” that provides the reason, that is, the<br />

reason that obligates us, to act with justice. We must also consider that, although several<br />

times he has rejected hope and fear as proper motives of obligation, they still play an<br />

important role.<br />

Whoever, indeed, does good out of love for God or neighbor, takes<br />

pleasure precisely in the action itself (such being the nature of love) and<br />

does not need any other incitement, or the command of a superior; To such<br />

97 Riley has simply ‘inclination.’<br />

98 D 4.280: “Atque hoc etiam non parum ad praxin verae pietatis facit: neque enim sufficit, ita nos Deo<br />

submissos esse, uti etiam tyranno obediremus; nec tantum timendus est ille ob magnitudinem, sed etiam<br />

amandus ob bonitatem; quae non magis a scriptura sacra, quam a recta ratione praecipiuntur. Atque huc<br />

ducunt meliora universalis jurisprudentiae principia, quae etiam cum sana theologia conspirant, & ad veram<br />

virtutem excitant. Tantumque abest, ut, qui non spe aut metu a superiore, sed propensione animi recte agit,<br />

juste non agat, ut ipse potissimum juste agat, quadam divinae justitiae humana imitatione.”<br />

99 This may of course raise the objection that God is necessitated, but not free, to act according to his<br />

nature. This is of course a contentious and well-trodden objection that I cannot take up at the point. Suffice<br />

it to say that Leibniz would say that God is free because completely determined by moral reason. I will<br />

explain this further in Chapter Seven.<br />

234

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!