28.06.2013 Views

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

. . .<br />

1. Everything just is possible for one who loves.<br />

2. Everything impossible for one who loves is unjust.<br />

3. Everything impossible for the lover is omissible.<br />

4. Everything unjust is contingent for those who love. 187<br />

The following phrases may be substituted for ‘love of all’: That is, “the one who loves all<br />

is one …”<br />

1. who is to enjoy (delectatur) the felicity of all.<br />

2. who perceives (sentit) the harmonious felicity of all.<br />

3. who in the felicity of all perceives identity weighed by difference. 188<br />

. . .<br />

The following substitutions also hold:<br />

1. for felicity: ‘optimal state’<br />

2. For state: ‘totality of accidents’<br />

3. For totality: ‘multiplicity of all’ 189<br />

In sum, the good person enjoys the optimal states of the multiplicity of accidents of<br />

everyone. These theorems and corollaries show how all definitions involving the good<br />

person are logically compatible. Leibniz calculates that the sum total of propositions,<br />

corollaries and substitutions derivable from the definition of ‘the good man’ is 1,485,600,<br />

any of which may be expanded by further consideration. It is unclear why knowing this<br />

helps, since it suggests that the demonstrative analysis he has just carried out is vastly<br />

incomplete. Nevertheless, his purpose is expressed at the very end of Draft 5: “Since the<br />

good person loves everyone, necessarily conflicts of love will always arise, and to clarify<br />

the outcome is the purpose of this whole doctrine.” 190 In sum, the purpose is to show that<br />

all notions contained in the definition of ‘the good person’ are compatible with the logic<br />

of ius. According to Leibniz’s methodology, since all definitions contained within the<br />

definition of ‘the good person’ are compatible, then the definition is true.<br />

Section 6: Concluding considerations<br />

What then does Leibniz accomplish in the Elementa? Leibniz provides an<br />

elaborate, if incomplete, response to the initial problem of justice (that justice is folly,<br />

since it enjoins us to do another’s good at one’s own expense). In the most general sense,<br />

justice means the constant will to bring about the harmonious felicity of everyone; or, the<br />

constant will to make one’s own happiness consistent with everyone else’s. His<br />

conclusions also point toward his later definition of justice as ‘charity of the wise.’<br />

According to definition, the good person must “know-well” (pernoscere) in order to<br />

187 A.6.1.477<br />

188 A.6.1.477<br />

189 A.6.1.477<br />

190 A.6.1.480: “Qvia cum vir bonus amet omnes, innumerabiles semper concursus amorum oriri necesse est,<br />

qvorum eventibus explicandis omnis haec doctrina impendenda est.”<br />

98

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!