28.06.2013 Views

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

whole, the vir bonus of the Elementa has become the sapientis of the Meditation. The<br />

good person whose possession of the moral qualities enabled her to “love everyone,” has<br />

come to possess the virtue enabling her to love everyone wisely. Although wisdom means<br />

“the science of felicity,” it also means the knowledge and will to act according to the<br />

rules of equality and equity.<br />

Section 4: Features of Leibniz’s Golden Rule<br />

Since Leibniz offers a rather unique version of the Golden Rule, and since he<br />

offers some clarifying remarks on his use of it, a closer look is warranted. Here is the rule<br />

once more:<br />

What you do not wish to have done to you, or what you do wish to have<br />

done to you, do not do to others, or do not deny to others. 77<br />

This version of the rule appears to be historically unique. It is found only here in the<br />

Meditation. It is not in the Bible, in Roman law, or anywhere else. Both Mollat and Riley<br />

refer this rule in Leibniz’s text to Matt. 7:12 and Luke 6:31. But those verses express only<br />

the positive form of the Rule. 78 As some commentators have noted, Leibniz’s version<br />

expresses both the negative and positive forms. 79 However, the positive form that it<br />

expresses is slightly different from the usual positive forms. It does not say ‘what you<br />

want done to yourself do to others, but rather, ‘what you want done to yourself do not<br />

deny to others.’ This formulation actually has a distinct logical advantage: you cannot do<br />

to others what you want done to yourself; you may only not deny them what you allow<br />

yourself. In this way, others have the right to refuse the sorts of things you wish for<br />

yourself, if they so wish. 80<br />

We might however be wary of using anything like the Golden Rule as a criterion<br />

for just actions, since there have long been valid and strong criticisms of it. Kant’s<br />

criticisms in the Grundlegung, of the negative version, are particularly noteworthy, in<br />

part because Leibniz seems to have anticipated them somewhat. Kant writes:<br />

Let it not be thought that the banal quod tibi non vis fieri, etc., could here<br />

serve as a guide or principle, for it is only derived from the principle [the<br />

moral law] and is restricted by various limitations. It cannot be a universal<br />

law, because it contains the ground neither of duties to one’s self nor of<br />

the duties of [beneficence] to others (for many a man would gladly<br />

consent that others should not benefit him, provided only that he might be<br />

77 M 57: “quod tibi non vis fieri, aut quod tibi vis fieri, neque aliis facito aut negato.”<br />

78 From the Vulgate: “quaecumque vultis ut faciant vobis homines et vos facite eis,” (do to others whatever<br />

you would have them do to you). The first part of Leibniz’s rule expresses the negative version, which does<br />

not appear in the NT but in OT (Tobit 4:16) and in the Regula Benedicti and Regula Magistri.<br />

79 See Brown, 1995, pp. 436-7.<br />

80 For example, under the traditional positive form of the rule a masochist could say, absurdly, ‘I want to be<br />

harmed, so, I should harm others.’ However, under Leibniz’s version the masochist cannot say this. He<br />

could only say,“I want to be harmed, therefore, I cannot deny to another the same desire to be harmed.”<br />

That means the masochist can harm another only if another consents. So, the masochist cannot use his<br />

desire to justify his treatment of others.<br />

226

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!