28.06.2013 Views

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

showed in the Elementa, love (or what he refers to here as the supreme conatus 12 ) is the<br />

means for fulfilling the obligation as determined by the definition of right. Love is the<br />

fulfillment of right and obligation, since it provides the right kind of motive, i.e., that<br />

which enables one to act simultaneously for the good for oneself and for another. But<br />

love is not itself the ground of obligation.<br />

Secondly, by mentioning love, the good person, and wisdom, the passage comes very<br />

close to defining justice as charity of the wise. Although justice is not mentioned in the<br />

passage, we can recall that Leibniz found love to be the nature of justice, and that the<br />

“good person” loves everyone in the most harmonious way, which means according to<br />

need and merit and without harming oneself.<br />

However, it was not until five years later that Leibniz first expressed his definition of<br />

justice as charity of the wise. 13 This occurred in a letter to one of his frequent<br />

correspondents, Herzog Johann Friedrich, in May of 1677. At the close of a series of brief<br />

remarks on a variety of topics, Leibniz writes, “I have discovered a secret inspiration.<br />

Demonstrations of natural jurisprudence out of this sole principle: justice is the charity of<br />

the wise.” 14 He does not explain how he came up with this new definition, but we can<br />

assume that it was already implied in the Elementa. In a later series of papers Leibniz<br />

attempted to work out this definition. In order to see how right forms the conceptual basis<br />

for justice as charity of the wise, we will now examine several of these papers.<br />

Section 3: The late 1670’s: Right, right reason, and justice as caritas sapientis<br />

The first paper to consider is titled (by the Akademie) “Modalia et Elementa Juris<br />

Naturalis” (1678). Overall, it attempts to establish the means for a “rightly ordered”<br />

justice. Of course, if justice is a virtue, then it must be a moderating disposition. But the<br />

question is, what is the rule for this moderation? Since wisdom is not mentioned here, the<br />

moderation seems to come from the “juris modalia” that were first introduced in the<br />

Elementa.<br />

Justice is rightly ordered charity, or virtue serving reason in the affections<br />

toward others endowed with reason. The good person is one who is<br />

endowed with justice. Every prudent person is a good person.<br />

The owed necessary<br />

Not-owed (is what for the good man is) contingent<br />

Permitted possibile<br />

Forbidden impossibile.<br />

Thus all propositions of modal logic can here be transferred. 15<br />

12<br />

Conatus is a very important concept and needs to be investigated; but it can be recalled that the Elementa<br />

defined it as “the beginning of action” (“Conatus est initium actionis” A.6.483). At one point he had<br />

defined justice as the constant conatus for the common felicity while saving oneself (“Iustitia est constans<br />

conatus ad felicitatem communem salva sua” A.6.1.454).<br />

13<br />

As recorded by Grua, pp. 203 and 211 in Jurisprudence Universelle et Théodicée selon Leibniz.<br />

14<br />

A.1.2.23: “Habe das arcanum motus gefunden. Demonstrationes de jurisprudentia naturali ex hoc solo<br />

principio: quod justitia sit caritas sapientis.”<br />

15<br />

A.6.4.2758: “Justitia est charitas recte ordinata seu virtus servans rationem in affectu erga alios<br />

ratione praeditos. Vir bonus est qui justitia praeditus est. Omnis prudens est vir bonus.<br />

106

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!