28.06.2013 Views

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

in the will, i.e., a dominant passion or habit. Given this possibility of moral failure,<br />

reason alone cannot compel us, but only guide us. To be just, one must develop the habit<br />

of conforming one’s will to the true propositions of right, which is to say, one must<br />

develop the virtue of justice. We are obliged, then, not only by the true meanings of the<br />

just, but by our moral-rational nature, by the very capacity we have for justice.<br />

Leibniz has maintained, since his initial formulation of the science of right, the<br />

idea that the moral qualities with which we are endowed enable us to be moral beings,<br />

i.e., to harmonize our ends with the ends of all other moral beings. This capacity has<br />

always implied that to be a moral agent entails self-limitation or self-mastery of the soul.<br />

This self-limitation, I suggest, may also be called autonomy. A certain, qualified, notion<br />

of autonomy, often cited by the modern natural lawyers, can be found in Romans 2: 15,<br />

which says that when we act by nature according to the law, we are “a law unto<br />

ourselves.” This is, however, not a fully developed notion of autonomy, since it is tied to<br />

instinctual motives. 116 Leibniz’s science of right, however, leads us to a second nature,<br />

that is, to virtue, bringing us close to a fully developed notion of autonomy or self-rule.<br />

According to this, to be determined by one’s own capacity for limiting one’s natural<br />

power, is just what it means to be a law unto oneself. In essence, this capacity is the<br />

capacity for a free will. A free will for Leibniz is not something that we have from the<br />

beginning. As self-rule, freedom is a function of the degree to which one determines<br />

oneself by moral principles. As we have seen, we are most free when we are most<br />

determined by right reasons. 117<br />

In the final chapter we will see more clearly how freedom and determination are<br />

related in Leibniz’s account of metaphysical and moral necessity. For two questions may<br />

arise in light of our conclusions: Is there any sense in which God is obligated, and if so,<br />

can we make sense of this being’s so-called freedom? These questions will be addressed<br />

in the final chapter.<br />

116 The concept of autonomy can be taken in a number of ways. For an excellent account of historical<br />

notions of autonomy and their development, see Schneewind (1998).<br />

117 Letter to Wedderkopf (1671): “Quod nihil detrahit libertati. Summa enim libertas est ad optimum a recta<br />

ratione cogi, qui aliam libertatem desiderat stultus est” (A.2.1.186).<br />

242

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!