28.06.2013 Views

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

examine the notion of “moral quality” more closely.<br />

While the passage from Grotius above indicates Leibniz’s likely source for the<br />

notion of moral quality as a subjective power, his direct source for it was his mathematics<br />

professor at Jena, Erhard Weigel. Leibniz himself explains the following: Weigel had<br />

distinguished three highest genera of entities: natural, moral, and notional. Under moral<br />

entity (entia morali) is a subgroup of moral qualities (qualitates morales), of which rights<br />

(jura) are one kind. 50 Pufendorf (whom Leibniz cites here, and who was also a student of<br />

Weigel) refers to this subgroup as “moral operative qualities” and identified them<br />

specifically as power, right, and obligation. 51 This means then, that the moral qualities are<br />

distinct from physical qualities, since they are in a genus distinct from natural (and<br />

notional) entities. 52 As a result, they denote the capacity of the agent to deliberate and act<br />

according to a just order, as well as the capacity for making moral claims against others. 53<br />

This capacity to act as well as to impose restrictions on acting characterizes the moral<br />

quality as “two-fold,” that is, as consisting of right and obligation—a power and a<br />

restriction upon power.<br />

Now let us consider the passage again. To recall the last line of §14a, above:<br />

“moral power is called Right and moral necessity is called Obligation.” These terms,<br />

right and obligation designate the two-fold (duplex) real quality of an action. Leibniz<br />

does not, however, explain the nature of this two-fold quality. In a much later text (1696)<br />

Leibniz asserts: “Right and obligation are not to be treated separately. They constitute<br />

one relation composed from both.” 54 Yet he does not explain the nature of this relation.<br />

As we have learned, right is the power to do what is just, and what is just is what serves<br />

public utility, while obligation is called moral necessity. But two quite critical questions<br />

remain (for Leibniz and for this dissertation): (1) What exactly is the relation between<br />

right and obligation? (2) What exactly grounds the necessity of obligation? In what<br />

follows I will suggest a preliminary answer to these questions.<br />

Regarding (1), there appears to be an analytic relation between the terms jus and<br />

50 As Leibniz explains in an earlier work, Specimen Quaestionum Philosophicarum (1664): “Jura ista<br />

H.Grot. J.B. et P. 1.1.4. appellat Qualitates morales tanquam si naturalibus contradistingueret. Et Cl mus<br />

Weigelius, Prof. Mathematum Jenensis, Praeceptor, Fautorque meus colendus tria summa genera Entium<br />

constituit: Naturale, Morale, et Notionale . . . . Jura igitur ad qualitates morales reducit, et uti actioni<br />

naturali seu motui Spatium substratum sit, spatium quoddam morale esse Statum, in quo quasi motus<br />

moralis exerceatur” (A.6.1.94).<br />

51 Pufendorf in On the Law of Nature and of Nations says that entia moralia are modes (thus qualities) of<br />

intelligent substances, “superadded” to them by God. They do not physically direct actions but only “make<br />

clear to men along what lines they should govern their liberty of action” (cited in Schneewind 2003, p.<br />

171). Pufendorf describes moral qualities as “moral operative qualities” and as either active or passive. “Of<br />

the former the most noble species are power, right, and obligation. Power is that by which a man is able to<br />

do something legally and with a moral effect. This effect is that an obligation is laid upon another to<br />

perform some task . . . or not to hinder another” (Schneewind 173). See Pufendorf’s de Jure Naturae et<br />

Gentium, 1.1.l, 1-21, or Leibniz’s citation: Elementa Jurisprudentiae, Bk. 1, def. 1.<br />

52 As Werner Schneiders claims, for Leibniz the concept ‘morality’ (moralitas) “designates the legal-moral<br />

judgeable quality of an action, in contrast to its mere physical quality; not some contrast between morality<br />

and legality (“Dieser Begriff [moralitas] bezeichnet die rechtlich-moralisch beurteilbare Qualität einer<br />

Handlung im Gegensatz zu ihrer bloß physischen Qualität; nicht etwas eine Moralität im Gegensatz zur<br />

Legalität” (Schneiders 609).<br />

53 See also Grua, Jurisprudence Universelle et Théodiée selon Leibniz (p. 227) and Schiedermair pp. 79-80.<br />

54 TI 802: “Jus et obligatio non sunt separanda in tractando. Constituunt unam relationem ex utroque<br />

compositam” (Notae in Tabulam Jurisprudentiae, 1696?).<br />

14

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!