28.06.2013 Views

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

Stony Brook University

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Leibniz has already revealed the “scandal” of voluntarism. Yet he invites his own scandal<br />

by invoking Grotius’ notorious claim that even if God did not exist, a “natural obligation”<br />

would still apply. 32 His point is that without God, there are still duties that follow from<br />

the natural right of self-preservation and well-being. Now, while these rights appear to<br />

impose only a prudential obligation (and arguably, an obligation to serve one’s own selfinterest<br />

is no real obligation), this is not the whole of Leibniz’s view. 33 As he says in the<br />

next sentence, “although, as I have observed, a natural law based on this source alone<br />

would be very imperfect” (RP 71). 34 This refers to his earlier statement, where he<br />

criticized Pufendorf for limiting the end of natural right to this life alone, thus making it<br />

valid for atheists. In view of this comment, then, Leibniz must temper his criticism of<br />

Pufendorf, since he believes that the fear of divine punishment is a powerful obligator,<br />

especially in the long term. This also means that Leibniz cannot wholly subscribe to<br />

Grotius’ notorious claim. 35 Yet a better explanation for Leibniz’s comment can be found<br />

elsewhere. As we have seen, the rules of natural right cannot be made exclusive to<br />

individual communities, such as a society of robbers, but must be valid for a universal<br />

community, at all times. 36<br />

Despite these concessions, Leibniz makes a striking counterpoint that gets to the<br />

heart of his own grounds of natural right: God is just, most just, precisely because he has<br />

no superior.<br />

To pass over all this, one must pay attention to this fact: that God is<br />

praised because he is just. There must be, then, a certain justice—or rather<br />

a supreme justice—in God, even though no one is superior to him, and he,<br />

by the spontaneity of his excellent nature, accomplishes all things well,<br />

such that no one can reasonably complain of him. (RP 71) 37<br />

ut taceam, quod Grotius bene notavit, fore aliquam naturalem obligationem, etsi daretur, quod dari non<br />

potest, Deum nullum esse, aut licet divina existentia seponatur tantisper; quoniam certé multa ab hominibus<br />

erga alios exigit propriae conservationis commoditatisque cura; quae Hobbius etiam pro parte annotavit; &<br />

hoc obligationis vinculum latronum societates exemplo suo confirmant, dum aliis hostes, inter se quaedam<br />

officia colere coguntur.”<br />

32 Grotius, De Jure Belli ac Pacis, prolegomena, sec. 11.<br />

33 For Grotius the natural law tells us how to manage the conflict between our natural sociability and our<br />

own benefit (paraphrasing Schneewind, IA p. 73) but this is not equivalent to saying that the natural law<br />

directs us simply to self-preservation, as it is for Hobbes—nor is it for Leibniz.<br />

34 D 4.280: “quamquam, ut jam notavi, imperfectum fit valde jus naturae, quod ex hoc solo fluat.”<br />

35 Leibniz’s agreement with Grotius on this point must be considerably qualified. In Theodicy (sec. 183-4),<br />

quoting and paraphrasing Bayle, Leibniz endorses the view of Aquinas and Grotius that we are “justified in<br />

saying that if there were no God we should nevertheless be obliged to conform to the natural law.” Yet, he<br />

continues, “one must not say, with some Scotists, that the eternal verities would exist even though there<br />

were no understanding, not even that of God. For it is, in my judgment, the divine understanding which<br />

gives reality to the eternal verities, albeit God’s will have no part therein. All reality must be founded on<br />

something existent. It is true that an atheist may be a geometrician: but if there were no God, geometry<br />

would have no object. And without God, not only would there be nothing existent, but there would be<br />

nothing possible.”<br />

36 See Nouveaux Essais p.89, quoted in Chapter Five, sec. 3.<br />

37 D 4.280: “haec, inquam, ut taceam, sciendum est, Deum ipsum laudari, quod justus est, adeoque esse<br />

quandam, immo potius esse summam ipsus Dei justitiam; etsi superiore careat, & sponte naturae excellentis<br />

onmia bene agat, ut nemo de eo cum ratione queri possit.”<br />

212

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!