02.03.2013 Views

Thinking and Deciding

Thinking and Deciding

Thinking and Deciding

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

ADAPTATION, CONTRAST, AND HEURISTICS 493<br />

we are better off if we believe that it is likely to occur, because we can savor it for a<br />

long time, but when the outcome is imminent we have little time to savor it, <strong>and</strong> our<br />

main concern is to avoid disappointment, so we are better off if we believe it is not<br />

likely to occur — if we “don’t get our hopes up.”<br />

Loewenstein <strong>and</strong> Linville tested this account by giving subjects a test that the<br />

subjects thought was related to intelligence. Half of the subjects were told that they<br />

would receive their scores immediately after the session, <strong>and</strong> the other half were<br />

told that they would receive their scores in two weeks. As the researchers predicted,<br />

the first group of subjects had lower expectations about their scores than the second<br />

group, <strong>and</strong>, as the end of the session approached, the expectations of subjects in<br />

the first group fell even more. (The experimenters did not ask the subjects in the<br />

second group about their expectations after the session.) In sum, this experiment<br />

suggests that we have desires concerning our hopes <strong>and</strong> disappointments <strong>and</strong> that we<br />

manipulate our expectations (deceive ourselves) to maximize the utility we derive<br />

from them. (Gilovich, Kerr, <strong>and</strong> Medvec, 1993, report similar results.)<br />

Although this experiment does not concern decision making, it does show that<br />

we have emotions concerning future outcomes <strong>and</strong> that we are concerned with these<br />

emotions as well as with the outcomes themselves. Some of these emotions, particularly<br />

the impatience that results from the contrast between our present state <strong>and</strong> a<br />

better state that we could choose to have very soon, could cause us to neglect our<br />

futures irrationally.<br />

Adaptation, contrast, <strong>and</strong> heuristics<br />

Psychologists have known for some time that experience establishes a reference<br />

point, against which future experiences are compared (Helson, 1964). This works<br />

for such sensations as that of heat <strong>and</strong> cold — a piece of metal at room temperature<br />

will feel warm to the touch of a h<strong>and</strong> just removed from ice water — <strong>and</strong> it seems to<br />

work for pleasure <strong>and</strong> displeasure as well. Most of us know about this, so we take<br />

care not to “ruin” the experience of going to our favorite restaurants or listening to<br />

our favorite pieces of music by doing these things repeatedly in quick succession. So<br />

we try to spread out good experiences.<br />

Because of the same adaptation effect, we also benefit more from improvement<br />

than from slow decline, given the same total level of pleasure averaged over time.<br />

With improvement, we benefit from the continuous pleasure to be derived from the<br />

contrast of our current state to the preceding state. Thus, although we discount future<br />

experiences, most people tend to want to get bad experiences over with. This might<br />

be a matter of avoiding dread, but it might also be a matter of preferring improvement.<br />

These two heuristics — spreading good outcomes out <strong>and</strong> preferring improvement<br />

over decline — are like other heuristics in that they are used even when they<br />

do not serve their purpose of maximizing the total utility of experiences. They generate<br />

some interesting framing effects, as shown by Loewenstein <strong>and</strong> Prelec (1993).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!