02.03.2013 Views

Thinking and Deciding

Thinking and Deciding

Thinking and Deciding

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

HYPOTHESES IN SCIENCE 167<br />

how the planetary motions could be explained more simply by assuming that the<br />

earth <strong>and</strong> the planets revolved around the sun, no crucial experiment or potential observation<br />

was known that could be used to demonstrate which of the two theories<br />

was superior. The Copernican theory won out, according to Lakatos, because this<br />

theory was more progressive as a program for research; one could ask <strong>and</strong> answer<br />

more questions within it than within the Ptolemaic theory. When Kepler assumed the<br />

Copernican theory was true, for example, he was able to show that planets moved in<br />

elliptical orbits, <strong>and</strong> Newton, in turn, showed how these ellipses could be explained<br />

by the inverse-square law of gravity.<br />

For Lakatos, then, a theory is useful if it generates valuable research. Lakatos’s<br />

view implies that theories cannot be compared directly with one another, to determine<br />

their closeness to truth or their probability. We can compare theories only in<br />

hindsight, after we have seen what research they generated. Again, this view is not<br />

useful advice to practicing scientists, unless they can foresee the future.<br />

We could, however, use probability theory (as we do with other hypotheses) to<br />

evaluate the effect of experimental results on hypotheses. By asking about the effect<br />

of various results on our hypotheses before we do an experiment, we can determine<br />

the value of the experiment before we do it. To find how the probability of a scientific<br />

hypothesis changes when we obtain an experimental result, we would assign a prior<br />

probability to each hypothesis, p(Hi) (where i takes a different value for each hypothesis).<br />

Observations <strong>and</strong> experimental results would constitute the data, the Dj s<br />

(with j taking different values for different results). After assigning a likelihood to<br />

each datum given each hypothesis, p(Dj |Hi), we could then use Bayes’s theorem to<br />

calculate the posterior probability of the hypothesis, p(Hi|Dj ). The data cannot, in<br />

science, be expected to raise the probability of a hypothesis precisely to one or lower<br />

it precisely to zero. Other things being equal, however, a good scientific experiment<br />

would be one with potential outcomes that have a high probability, given some<br />

hypothesis, <strong>and</strong> a low probability given others. If we obtain such a result, our probabilities<br />

for the various hypotheses would change greatly, <strong>and</strong> we would, therefore,<br />

have learned a lot.<br />

Probability theory would constitute part of the normative theory of science. The<br />

other part of the normative theory would be the theory of decision making, which<br />

is explored in Part III. 4 The theory is normative but not necessarily prescriptive.<br />

Although scientists can, <strong>and</strong> sometimes do, calculate probabilities as specified by<br />

this theory, they can probably do nearly as well by following certain prescriptive<br />

rules of thumb, which we shall discuss shortly.<br />

This normative theory can help us to underst<strong>and</strong> why the prescriptive advice of<br />

Popper <strong>and</strong> Platt, on how to formulate <strong>and</strong> test scientific hypotheses, is good advice<br />

when it is possible to follow it. For Popper, a good result (D, datum) is one that has<br />

a probability of 1, given the hypothesis being tested (H), <strong>and</strong> a very low probability<br />

4 This view — that the normative theory of science consists of probability theory <strong>and</strong> decision theory<br />

— is advocated by Horwich, 1982, especially pp. 1–15, 51–63, <strong>and</strong> 100–136. I expressed my own support<br />

for it earlier in Rationality <strong>and</strong> Intelligence, 1985a, ch. 4. Its first clear expression seems to be in Savage<br />

(1954, ch. 6).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!