02.03.2013 Views

Thinking and Deciding

Thinking and Deciding

Thinking and Deciding

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

UTILITARIANISM AS A NORMATIVE MODEL 399<br />

theory itself does. Many writers speak of utility as the satisfaction of preferences.<br />

The term “preference” suggests a decision, however, <strong>and</strong> we have found that our<br />

decisions are not always the ones that best achieve our goals. It does not do people<br />

any good to give them something they “prefer” now but that will in the future prevent<br />

them from achieving their goals. Our personal goals, together with our beliefs about<br />

the effects of our choices, are the reasons for our preferences, as expressed in our<br />

decisions. Other writers speak of utility as the satisfaction of desires. The term<br />

“satisfaction,” however, suggests an emotion that we experience only after our goal<br />

is achieved, <strong>and</strong>, as I pointed out in Chapter 10, for many of our important goals we<br />

cannot have this experience (for example, our goal that our children have a long <strong>and</strong><br />

happy life after we die). I shall therefore continue to assume that our main concern<br />

is with the achievement of our personal goals.<br />

Some forms of utilitarianism consider effects of choices on the satisfaction of<br />

rational preferences only, those preferences that people would have on reflection.<br />

But the form of reflection is not usually specified. An implication of the view I<br />

present here is that the relevant sort of reflection is about the distinction between<br />

fundamental values <strong>and</strong> means values (p. 342). We should try to achieve means<br />

values only to the extent to which they are connected to fundamental values by true<br />

belief. We would endorse this principle because it is our fundamental values that<br />

matter, by definition.<br />

Does utilitarianism require calculation?<br />

When we use utilitarian concepts in our everyday reasoning, however, we do not<br />

need to be so precise in our expression. We often speak of “paying attention to other<br />

people’s feelings” when we are trying to emphasize the basic message of utilitarianism,<br />

that what matters in our decision making is the consequences of what we do for<br />

people (not just the people near to us but those distant in time <strong>and</strong> space as well).<br />

Because of its resemblance to the biblical rule “And as ye would that men should<br />

do unto you, do ye also to them likewise” (Luke 6:31, also Matthew 7:12), Hare<br />

(1963, chs. 6 <strong>and</strong> 7) calls this sort of thinking a “Golden Rule argument.”<br />

Interpersonal comparison<br />

Utilitarianism requires comparison of one person’s utilities with another person’s.<br />

Does this make sense?<br />

For example, suppose you are in charge of a college residence <strong>and</strong> you must decide<br />

when to allow John to play his stereo in the residence (<strong>and</strong> at what volume) <strong>and</strong><br />

when he should not. To do this, you would put yourself in the position of John (who<br />

wants to hear his records) <strong>and</strong> also of the person he might be bothering (Judy, who<br />

lives in the room below). You would ask whose good (utility) is greater: John’s, to<br />

hear his music, or Judy’s, to get her work done. Because moral judgments are impersonal,<br />

it does not matter what particular individuals are involved; the answer should<br />

be the same even if John <strong>and</strong> Judy switched places. (When they switch places, they

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!