02.03.2013 Views

Thinking and Deciding

Thinking and Deciding

Thinking and Deciding

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

380 QUANTITATIVE JUDGMENT<br />

Anchoring <strong>and</strong> underadjustment<br />

We often make numerical judgments by anchoring on some number <strong>and</strong> then adjusting<br />

for other things that we know. The anchoring <strong>and</strong> adjustment heuristic affects<br />

quantitative estimates of all sorts. In general, people tend to underadjust. They do<br />

this even when the anchor is totally irrelevant to the judgment. For example, Tversky<br />

<strong>and</strong> Kahneman (1974) asked subjects to estimate certain proportions, such as the<br />

percentage of African countries in the United Nations. “For each quantity, a number<br />

between 0 <strong>and</strong> 100 was determined by spinning a wheel of fortune in the subject’s<br />

presence. The subject was instructed to indicate first whether that number was higher<br />

or lower than the value of the quantity, <strong>and</strong> then to estimate the value of the quantity<br />

by moving upward or downward from the given number” (p. 1128).<br />

The number the subject started with, determined solely by the spin of a wheel,<br />

had a marked effect on the final estimate. Subjects who got high numbers from the<br />

wheel gave higher estimates than those who got low numbers. The adjustment was<br />

insufficient. This effect is found even when the subject needed only to attend to<br />

the anchor (for example, by rewriting it); it does not require an initial judgment of<br />

whether the anchor is too high or too low (Wilson, Houston, Etling, <strong>and</strong> Brekke,<br />

1996). Of course, when the number is not arbitrary, the effect is even larger. One<br />

practical consequence of this effect is in the domain of liability law. The plaintiff’s<br />

request for damages in a lawsuit influences the jury’s award (Chapman <strong>and</strong> Bornstein,<br />

1996), even though, in principle, the size of the damage award should depend<br />

only on the facts presented. Apparently, the jury anchors on the request.<br />

There is nothing wrong (in principle) with forming an estimate by starting with<br />

one value <strong>and</strong> then adjusting it successively as each new piece of information comes<br />

to mind. The mistake that subjects make is not adjusting enough. Underadjustment,<br />

in turn, may result from a failure to look for counterevidence, a failure of actively<br />

open-minded thinking. Chapman <strong>and</strong> Johnson (1999) asked subjects to think of features<br />

of the target item that were different from the anchor, <strong>and</strong> this reduced the<br />

underadjustment effect. When the subjects tried to think of features of the target that<br />

were similar to the answer, the effect did not change. This phenomenon supports the<br />

claim I made (in Chapter 3) that we tend to be biased in favor of our present beliefs,<br />

even when these beliefs are induced in an experiment. We do not take sufficient<br />

account of evidence against them. In this kind of experiment, subjects could manifest<br />

this bias by searching their memories for evidence consistent with the initial<br />

estimate, or anchor, even though they know that this estimate is completely arbitrary.<br />

Simple heuristics for judgment<br />

People use a variety of simple heuristics for judgment. These heuristics take less<br />

time than a full MAUT analysis would take, by far. We have evidence for some of<br />

these heuristics. Others have the status of models that fit the data, but possibly only<br />

as approximations, just as linear models fit despite the fact that people probably do<br />

not think like computers following linear models.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!