02.03.2013 Views

Thinking and Deciding

Thinking and Deciding

Thinking and Deciding

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

UTILITARIANISM AS A NORMATIVE MODEL 403<br />

explicitly argue this position. Others may truly believe that such wars are always<br />

ineffective. These beliefs, however, may sometimes arise from the belief-overkill<br />

phenomenon discussed in Chapter 9.<br />

Many modern deontologists trace their roots to Immanuel Kant’s (1785/1983)<br />

categorical imperative. Kant argued that moral principles had to be categorical (required<br />

in all cases) rather than “hypothetical” (dependent on other desires). Thus,<br />

the reason to keep promises should not depend on the motive of inculcating trust.<br />

The justification must come from “reason” alone. One statement of the Categorical<br />

Imperative was “Act only on that maxim through which you can at the same time<br />

will that it should become a universal law.” Thus, making a false promise whenever<br />

it suits you to do so (for example, borrowing money without intending to pay it back)<br />

would not fit. If it were a universal law to do this, promises would be meaningless.<br />

So it is inconsistent to follow such a maxim.<br />

Kant’s categorical imperative is often confused with the generalization test: “Do<br />

whatever would be best if everyone did it,” or “Follow the rule (maxim) that would<br />

best for everyone to follow.” The idea is to evaluate moral principles by asking “What<br />

if everybody did that?” Most scholars do not think that this is what Kant had in mind,<br />

but it is a popular approach to morality. One possible maxim is “Do whatever does<br />

the most good.” This is, of course, the utilitarian rule. If everybody did that, then the<br />

most good would be done.<br />

Other deontological rules are based on the injunction not to use people as means,<br />

but to treat everyone as an end. This would seem to prohibit any form of hurting<br />

some to help others. Kant’s second formulation of the Categorical Imperative reads:<br />

“Act so that you treat humanity, whether in your own person or in that of another, [1]<br />

always as an end <strong>and</strong> [2] never as a means only” (Kant, 1785/1983). The negative<br />

injunction “never as a means only” has been the source of much speculation. Because<br />

it contains the word “only,” it is fully consistent with the utilitarian view, which<br />

simply holds that those used as means must also be considered as part of the overall<br />

accounting. But a utilitarian would also find the injunction to be redundant. When<br />

everyone is considered as an end, we weigh the interests of some against the interest<br />

of others, <strong>and</strong> often we have no choice but to settle for the lesser harm. Perhaps Kant<br />

was drawing on a more common intuition against the idea of using people as means<br />

at all.<br />

The same principle may be part of the doctrine of the double effect in Catholicism,<br />

attributed to Thomas Aquinas (1947, II–II, Q. 64, art. 7) as part of his explanation<br />

of why killing in self-defense can be morally acceptable:<br />

Nothing hinders one act from having two effects, only one of which<br />

is intended, while the other is beside the intention. Now moral acts<br />

take their species according to what is intended, <strong>and</strong> not according to<br />

what is beside the intention, since this is accidental.... Accordingly<br />

the act of self-defense may have two effects, one is the saving of one’s<br />

life, the other is the slaying of the aggressor. Therefore this act, since<br />

one’s intention is to save one’s own life, is not unlawful, seeing that it

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!