02.03.2013 Views

Thinking and Deciding

Thinking and Deciding

Thinking and Deciding

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

390 MORAL JUDGMENT AND CHOICE<br />

We thus speak of moral intuitions, rather than heuristics. But, like heuristics, they<br />

may be slightly off, producing good results — corresponding to the reasons people<br />

have for wanting each other to follow them — in some cases <strong>and</strong> less good results<br />

in others. I shall thus take the view that we can talk about biases in moral judgment,<br />

just as elsewhere. And I shall assume a simple normative model.<br />

In this chapter <strong>and</strong> those to follow, I shall take the view that utility theory can be<br />

extended straightforwardly to deal with choices that affect the utility of many people.<br />

This amounts to utilitarianism, a controversial moral philosophy first systematized<br />

by Jeremy Bentham in the eighteenth century (1789) <strong>and</strong> developed further by John<br />

Stuart Mill (1863), Henry Sidgwick (1874/1962), Richard M. Hare (1981), John<br />

Broome (1991), Peter Singer (1993) <strong>and</strong> others. I shall not fully defend this theory<br />

here. But it has the advantage of being fully consistent with other ways of developing<br />

utility theory, such as expected utility theory. And even those who do not accept it<br />

may find it useful for analyzing the consequences of choices.<br />

It might seem possible to bypass moral questions entirely. Instead of this chapter,<br />

I could have a chapter about “good decisions that affect other people.” I could<br />

argue that we analyze such decisions simply by extending utility theory to cover<br />

these cases, without mentioning the fact that this extension amounts to utilitarianism,<br />

which is traditionally part of moral philosophy rather than decision theory. The<br />

trouble with such an effort to bypass moral judgment is that morality in general (utilitarian<br />

or not) concerns itself with the very same decisions ...,maybe not all of them,<br />

but a lot of them. Often, when someone argues for some policy on the ground that it<br />

has the best overall expected consequences (i.e., maximizes expected utility), someone<br />

else will argue that the policy is immoral. Thus, we cannot avoid a discussion of<br />

morality <strong>and</strong> what it is. Utilitarians, of course, see no conflict between morality <strong>and</strong><br />

“good decision making” in general.<br />

What are moral judgments?<br />

We can begin to underst<strong>and</strong> morality by asking about the functions that it serves.<br />

Morality involves telling each other what we should do, or otherwise trying to influence<br />

each other’s decision making. We can express morality, as a way of influencing<br />

others, in several ways: teaching principles directly by explaining them or by expressing<br />

moral emotions; setting examples of how to behave; gossiping (<strong>and</strong> thereby<br />

expressing principles by presupposing them when we criticize others — seeSabini<br />

<strong>and</strong> Silver, 1981); rewarding behavior that follows the principles <strong>and</strong> punishing behavior<br />

that violates them; supporting or violating institutional (family, governmental)<br />

laws or rules (depending on what we think of their morality); supporting or opposing<br />

such laws or rules, making or repealing them; or justifying them in hindsight by<br />

referring to norms, which are then supported by the appeal. The concept of morality<br />

can be seen as arising as an abstraction from all of these situations (Singer, 1982).<br />

Although “morality” may have other meanings, this is the meaning that is relevant to<br />

decision making.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!