02.03.2013 Views

Thinking and Deciding

Thinking and Deciding

Thinking and Deciding

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

CONCLUSION 339<br />

win the $100, if all get the gamble. We can often describe tradeoffs across people as<br />

gambles for individuals.<br />

Another way of stating the third problem is that decisions made according to<br />

one measure can sometimes make everyone worse off according to another measure<br />

(Kaplow <strong>and</strong> Shavell, 2002). According to the PTO, in the last example, it would<br />

be better to give everyone a gamble with a .7 chance of winning $100 than to give<br />

everyone $50. Yet the $50 is better for each person according to the st<strong>and</strong>ard gamble<br />

method (which we could assume to be a measure of individual utility). So, by<br />

following the results of the PTO, we make everyone worse off.<br />

A fourth problem is that the suggested solution does not work. This is a mere<br />

fact, however. The other reasons would apply even if it worked. The solution does<br />

not work because methods of utility assessment are internally inconsistent. The internal<br />

inconsistencies also seem to have a lot to do with the disagreements between<br />

methods.<br />

For example, we have seen (in Chapter 11) that the distortion of utilities in SG<br />

can be explained in terms of the π function of prospect theory. This produced a<br />

certainty effect, which makes the utility of money more sharply declining than it<br />

would otherwise be. The same function can explain internal inconsistencies within<br />

gambles.<br />

The PTO shows another kind of internal inconsistency, ratio inconsistency. Subjects<br />

are unresponsive to changes in the ratios of conditions being compared. For<br />

example, a subject will say that 40 people becoming blind <strong>and</strong> deaf (BBDD) is just<br />

as bad as 100 people becoming blind (BB). The subject will also say that 20 people<br />

becoming BB is just as bad as 100 people becoming blind in one eye (B). These judgments<br />

would imply that BB is .4 as bad as BBDD, <strong>and</strong> B is .2 as bad as BB. Thus, B<br />

should be .08 as bad as BBDD. If we ask how many people becoming BBDD is as<br />

bad as 100 people becoming B, we should get an answer of 8. In this kind of task, the<br />

answers are usually much higher, for example, 16. It is impossible to know which<br />

judgment is best from this information alone, but we know the three judgments, 40,<br />

20, <strong>and</strong> 16, are inconsistent with each other. Consistency could be restored either<br />

by moving the 40 up to 80 or the 16 down to 8, or other ways. The problem is that<br />

the judgments are not far enough apart (Ubel, De Kay, Baron, <strong>and</strong> Asch, 1996a).<br />

Depending on which conditions are used, this effect could make the PTO disagree<br />

in various directions with the results of other methods. This effect could result from<br />

the tendency to spread out judgments evenly, described on p. 320.<br />

Conclusion<br />

It may seem that utility measurement is beset with so many problems that it is hopeless.<br />

The various methods of measurement are internally inconsistent <strong>and</strong> inconsistent<br />

with each other. There are two responses to this negative assessment. First,<br />

“compared to what?” Alternative methods of allocating resources, which rely on direct<br />

intuitive judgments about the decisions in question, are very likely even worse

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!