02.03.2013 Views

Thinking and Deciding

Thinking and Deciding

Thinking and Deciding

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

264 DESCRIPTIVE THEORY OF CHOICE UNDER UNCERTAINTY<br />

Figure 11.1: π, the weight applied to the utility of each outcome, as a function of p,<br />

the probability of the outcome, according to prospect theory (based on Tversky <strong>and</strong><br />

Kahneman, 1992).<br />

pay for, say, a fourth ticket if they already had three (which would only increase an<br />

intermediate possibility of winning).<br />

An interesting consequence of the π function is shown in the following problem<br />

(based on Tversky <strong>and</strong> Kahneman, 1981, p. 455):<br />

Consider the following two-stage game. In the first stage, there is a<br />

.75 probability of ending the game without winning anything, <strong>and</strong> a .25<br />

chance to move into the second stage. If you reach the second stage, you<br />

have a choice between ($30) <strong>and</strong> ($45, .80). However, you must make<br />

this choice before either stage of the game is played.<br />

Most subjects think about this problem in the same way as they thought about the<br />

choice of ($30) versus ($45, .80). They therefore choose ($30). These are the same<br />

subjects who chose ($45, .20) over ($30, .25), however. Think about the two-stage<br />

gambles for a moment, though. If you calculate the overall probability of $30, assuming<br />

that that option is chosen, it is .25, the probability of getting to the second<br />

stage. Likewise, the probability of $45, if that option is chosen, is (.25) (.80) (the<br />

probability of getting to the second stage multiplied by the probability of winning if<br />

you get there), or .20. Therefore, the probabilities of the outcomes in the two-stage<br />

gambles are identical to the probabilities of the outcomes in the gambles ($30, .25)<br />

<strong>and</strong> ($45, .20), yet the common pattern of choices is reversed.<br />

Subjects who show this kind of reversal (as many do) are violating what Kahneman<br />

<strong>and</strong> Tversky (1984) call the principle of invariance. The invariance principle

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!