02.03.2013 Views

Thinking and Deciding

Thinking and Deciding

Thinking and Deciding

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

52 THE STUDY OF THINKING<br />

ably are not. They could simply be the results of exposure to certain cultural st<strong>and</strong>ards,<br />

or they could have been formulated by individuals <strong>and</strong> used uncritically for<br />

so many years that they have come to be accepted as truth. Although most people<br />

in our culture agree that killing <strong>and</strong> stealing are wrong, for example, we disagree<br />

strongly about whether premarital sex, abortion, or euthanasia are right or wrong.<br />

When intuitions disagree like this, someone’s intuition must be wrong.<br />

Often, as in the problem about the six children presented at the beginning of the<br />

chapter, intuition yields easily to convincing arguments such as those based on mathematics.<br />

These arguments frequently concern the purpose of the normative model in<br />

question, for example, having accurate beliefs. In other cases the arguments for some<br />

principle are less comprehensible or less compelling, than are, say, mathematical arguments<br />

about probability theory, but the arguments may still be correct. Intuitions<br />

are often useful evidence in philosophical reflection, but they are not the last word.<br />

I shall take the view that normative models result from imposing an analytical<br />

framework on reality <strong>and</strong> from working out the implications of that framework.<br />

Arithmetic is an example. Why do we think that one plus one is two? It is not a<br />

fact about the world, but of a system that we impose on the world whether the world<br />

fits or not. When we watch raindrops fall on a windowpane, we often see that they<br />

merge. One raindrop plus one raindrop can make one big raindrop, not two. You may<br />

be tempted to say that this isn’t fair. We say it isn’t fair because drops falling on top<br />

of each other do not count as “addition.” We do not apply the framework this way.<br />

But why not? The answer is that, once we have adopted the framework, we force the<br />

world into it. Drops falling on top of each other doesn’t count exactly because, if it<br />

did, we would have to give up the framework. If we have to do too much forcing,<br />

or exclude too many things, then the framework seems less useful, <strong>and</strong> we look for<br />

another one. But once we have adopted a framework, we can deduce conclusions<br />

from it, just as many of the conclusions of mathematics can be deduced from a few<br />

simple principles of sets <strong>and</strong> arithmetic, principles that we impose on the world.<br />

I will use a similar kind of imposed framework in analyzing decisions. For example,<br />

I will analyze some decisions into options, unknown states of the world, <strong>and</strong><br />

outcomes. Once we adopt this framework, many normative conclusions will follow.<br />

Arguments about normative models should be about the applicability of such<br />

frameworks, as opposed to alternatives.<br />

Many people find the idea of normative models bothersome. They think that, if<br />

most people violate some model in some situation, then the model could not be truly<br />

normative in that situation. The majority cannot be wrong, they think, <strong>and</strong> we should<br />

adjust the normative model to fit what people do. There is a point to this argument.<br />

People who tried to develop normative models have made mistakes, <strong>and</strong> a normative<br />

model is more likely to be a mistake if most people violate it than if most follow it, so<br />

a lack of fit with behavior is first-blush evidence that something might be wrong with<br />

the application of the model to the situation in question. We should look carefully<br />

for such errors. But the evidence is only first blush. We cannot adjust the model<br />

just because it doesn’t fit behavior, or we risk undercutting its entire purpose, which<br />

is to determine how our behavior subverts the achievement of our own goals. The

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!