02.03.2013 Views

Thinking and Deciding

Thinking and Deciding

Thinking and Deciding

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

318 UTILITY MEASUREMENT<br />

we can meaningfully ask how we can minimize this error. We shall thus distinguish<br />

here between judged utility <strong>and</strong> true utility.<br />

Direct versus indirect judgments<br />

The simplest methods for measuring utility are direct. In these methods, the subject<br />

simply makes a judgment of the utility of one object as a proportion of the utility<br />

of another, or adjusts the end of one interval so that it is equal to another. Note that<br />

such matching responses need not involve hypothetical decisions. Another way to<br />

do this, which we shall examine later, is to make rating responses to stimuli that vary<br />

on several dimensions. For example, subjects can rate the badness of situations involving<br />

combinations of health states (X) <strong>and</strong> monetary losses (Y). We can compare<br />

the utility of X <strong>and</strong> Y by asking how much Y is needed to compensate for a given<br />

loss of X, so as to make the average rating the same.<br />

Indirect judgments are based on hypothetical decisions. They thus represent decision<br />

utility (as opposed to predicted utility). For example, in the time-tradeoff<br />

(TTO) method, the subject indicates how many years of future life with normal vision<br />

is just as good as fifty years with blindness. The idea here is to assume that the<br />

subject makes decisions based on utility <strong>and</strong> to infer the utility from the decision.<br />

If the subject says forty years, <strong>and</strong> if we assume that utility adds up over time, then<br />

we can conclude that the subject’s utility for blindness is .8, on a scale where death<br />

is 0 <strong>and</strong> life with normal vision is 1. This is because .8 · 50 = 1 · 40. Or, in the<br />

person-tradeoff (PTO) method, we can ask how many cases of blindness is just as<br />

bad as ten deaths. If death is five times as bad as blindness, <strong>and</strong> if the judgment is<br />

based on adding utility across people, then the answer should be fifty.<br />

When subjects make indirect judgments, they do it in two ways. In one way,<br />

they make a direct judgment <strong>and</strong> then infer their indirect judgment from that. For<br />

example, when they are asked (in the person tradeoff method) how many people<br />

losing a finger is equivalent to ten people losing an arm, they may ask themselves,<br />

“How many times worse is it to lose an arm than a finger,” <strong>and</strong> then they multiply<br />

this by ten. In the other way, they think about the people, not the badness of the<br />

losses. Indirect judgments can be seen as a form of predicted utility, as distinct from<br />

decision utility.<br />

We may summarize the situation as follows:<br />

True Utility ✏✏✏✏✏✏✶<br />

<br />

Decision Utility<br />

✻<br />

❄<br />

Judged Utility<br />

Judgment<br />

✏✏✏✏✏✏✶ Here, True Utility represents the actual outcome evaluated in terms of the subject’s<br />

ultimate criteria. Decision Utility represents what is inferred from decisions. Judged

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!