02.03.2013 Views

Thinking and Deciding

Thinking and Deciding

Thinking and Deciding

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

242 NORMATIVE THEORY OF CHOICE UNDER UNCERTAINTY<br />

changing the unit) would just multiply the difference between EUA <strong>and</strong> EUB by the<br />

same constant, but its direction would not change. If A were higher (better) than B,<br />

it would still be better.<br />

Pascal advocated this sort of analysis as what we would call a normative theory<br />

of decision making in general. Implicit in his approach is the decomposition of decisions<br />

into states, options, <strong>and</strong> outcomes (or consequences). To each state we can<br />

assign a number expressing our personal probability judgment, <strong>and</strong> to each outcome<br />

we can assign a number representing its utility. Once we have made these assignments,<br />

we can calculate the expected utility of each option (or compare the expected<br />

utilities of two options, as in 16.3) by a method completely analogous to the calculation<br />

of the expected value of gambles.<br />

A numerical utility estimate, as used in this kind of analysis, is not something that<br />

exists in the head, to be read off as if from a thermometer. It is, rather, a judgment of<br />

the desirability of an outcome, made (ideally) as if the judge knew all relevant facts<br />

about the outcome. Utility judgments are useful for making important decisions.<br />

We must remember, however, that expected-utility theory is a normative model, not<br />

a prescriptive one. If we tried to calculate expected utilities for every decision we<br />

make, we would spend our whole lives making calculations. Instead of doing this,<br />

we adopt prescriptive rules of various sorts, including rules of personal behavior <strong>and</strong><br />

rules of morality. If these rules are good ones, they will usually prescribe the same<br />

decisions that we would make if we had time to carry out a more thorough analysis.<br />

Other examples of comparison of errors<br />

The basic idea of Pascal’s wager was that some errors are much worse than others.<br />

Analogous situations occur in the courtroom, as illustrated by the quotation that<br />

begins this chapter. We find it worse to convict innocent people of crimes than to<br />

let the guilty go free. As a result, we require a high st<strong>and</strong>ard of proof in order to<br />

convict someone. In common law, it is usually said that a person must be guilty “beyond<br />

a reasonable doubt.” Expected utility theory can help us capture this idea more<br />

precisely. Consider the following table:<br />

State of the world<br />

Option Innocent Guilty<br />

Convict −100 0<br />

Acquit 0 −10<br />

The numbers in the cells represent utilities. We assume that convicting the guilty<br />

<strong>and</strong> acquitting the innocent have utilities of 0. We could, of course, add a constant<br />

to each column, <strong>and</strong> no conclusion would change. The table indicates that a false<br />

conviction is ten times worse than a false acquittal. What does this ratio imply about<br />

the appropriate interpretation of “beyond a reasonable doubt?” In particular, at what

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!