02.03.2013 Views

Thinking and Deciding

Thinking and Deciding

Thinking and Deciding

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

524 RISK<br />

tant in explaining socially important forms of risky behavior, such as crime, abuse<br />

of drugs <strong>and</strong> alcohol, gambling, reckless driving, <strong>and</strong> violent conflict. Perhaps the<br />

same factors can explain pathologies of excessive risk aversion such as anxiety <strong>and</strong><br />

obsessive behavior. Perhaps these factors play some role. But the studies that describe<br />

these effects are about thinking, in which people consider the alternatives <strong>and</strong><br />

draw conclusions. Much of the harmful behavior of interest is not the result of thinking.<br />

If anything, it is rationalized after the fact, but more often it is simply regretted.<br />

Behavior is surely affected by factors other than thought (Loewenstein, 1996).<br />

Conclusion<br />

This chapter has presented several examples of parallel findings from laboratory<br />

studies <strong>and</strong> examination of actual public decisions about risk. Societies have several<br />

ways of dealing with risk: individual consumer behavior, lawsuits, laws, <strong>and</strong><br />

regulations. All these ways seem to express common intuitions about risk. These intuitions<br />

oppose risks that are involuntary, catastrophic, unknown, caused by action,<br />

or artificial. Intuitions favor reducing risks to zero. In the case of involuntary risks,<br />

normative theory <strong>and</strong> intuition are on the same side. In other cases, normative theory<br />

seems to be neutral, <strong>and</strong> people seem to be biased toward one side. These biases are<br />

found in laboratory studies with questionnaires as well as in the real world.<br />

We can avoid the deleterious effects of intuitive thinking if we learn to think<br />

quantitatively. This does not mean that we must have numbers. It does mean that we<br />

realize that a well-made decision requires comparisons of quantities. If we have a<br />

feeling for the quantities, we can make a good guess at what the decision would be<br />

even if we do not know the numbers themselves. This is what we do all the time in<br />

other domains. Tennis players, for example, realize that the intended placement of a<br />

shot is based on a tradeoff of the probability of its going out <strong>and</strong> the probability of<br />

its winning the point if it does not go out. They do not know these probabilities as<br />

a function of where they aim, although some tennis statistician could, in principle,<br />

compile them. They do, however, think in this quantitative way even without the<br />

numbers.<br />

Quantitative thinking of this sort is not widespread. People do not even notice<br />

its absence. Many people, for example, say that decisions are “difficult” because<br />

there are costs as well as benefits. Many of these people do not seem to consider the<br />

possibility of looking at some overall measure, such as death rates or life expectancy,<br />

or doing something like a decision analysis.<br />

The same goes for government regulation, such as regulation of clean air. If, for<br />

example, we ask people how much money they are willing to pay to prevent one person<br />

from getting asthma or emphysema, the answer is a fair amount. The same for<br />

the time they are willing to spend. They may be telling the truth. Yet when the U.S.<br />

Congress passed a revision of the Clean Air Act <strong>and</strong> the Environmental Protection<br />

Administration (EPA) proposed new regulations requiring extra inspections of motor<br />

vehicles, people rose up in anger at intrusive government regulation. Exasperated of-

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!