02.03.2013 Views

Thinking and Deciding

Thinking and Deciding

Thinking and Deciding

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

244 NORMATIVE THEORY OF CHOICE UNDER UNCERTAINTY<br />

greater extent, in the long run, than any other rule. Although this argument turns out<br />

to be weak, it may help to explain the immediate appeal of expected-utility theory.<br />

To see this, consider the analogy between expected value (formula 1), <strong>and</strong> expected<br />

utility (formula 2). In both cases, we are trying to maximize something. In<br />

one case, it is wealth; in the other, it is utility. In both cases, we will do better in the<br />

long run by making all of our decisions in agreement with the formula than by any<br />

other method at our disposal. (Remember, we cannot see into the future.)<br />

If, for example, I have a choice between $4.00 if a heart is drawn <strong>and</strong> $1.00 if any<br />

red card (heart or diamond) is drawn, the expected value of the first option ($1.00) is<br />

higher than that of the second ($0.50). In the long run — if I am offered this choice<br />

over <strong>and</strong> over — I am bound to do better by taking the first option every time than by<br />

any other policy. I will win 25% of the times when I choose the first option, so I will<br />

average $1.00 each time I choose it. I will win 50% of the times when I choose the<br />

second option, but my average winning will be only $0.50. Any way of playing that<br />

tells me to choose the second option on some plays of the game will lead to a lower<br />

total payoff on those plays. In a sufficiently large number of plays, I will do best to<br />

choose the first option every time.<br />

The same reasoning can be applied if I am faced with many different kinds of<br />

decisions. Even if the amount to be won <strong>and</strong> the probability of winning change from<br />

decision to decision, my total wealth will be highest at the end if I choose the larger<br />

expected value every time.<br />

Similarly, if utility measures the extent of my goal achievement, if I can add up<br />

utilities from different decisions just as I can add up my monetary winnings from<br />

gambling, <strong>and</strong> if I maximize expected utility for every decision, then, over the long<br />

run, I will achieve my goals more fully than I could by following any other policy.<br />

The same reasoning applies when we consider decisions made by many people.<br />

If a great many people make decisions in a way that maximizes the expected utility<br />

of each decision, then all these people together will achieve their goals more fully<br />

than they will with any other policy. This extension of the argument to many people<br />

becomes relevant when we reflect on the fact that sometimes the “long run” is not so<br />

long for an individual. Decisions like Pascal’s Wager are not repeated many times<br />

in a lifetime. Even for once-in-a-lifetime decisions, the expected-utility model maximizes<br />

everyone’s achievement of his goals, to the extent to which everyone follows<br />

the model. Moreover, if we give advice to many people (as I am implicitly doing as<br />

I write this), the best advice is to maximize expected utility, because that will lead to<br />

the best outcomes for the group of advice recipients as a whole.<br />

Can we add utilities from the outcomes of different decisions, just as we add<br />

together monetary winnings? Three points need to be made. First, this idea requires<br />

that we accept a loss in utility at one time — or for one person — for the sake of a<br />

greater gain at another time — or for another person. If I am offered the game I have<br />

described, in which I have a .25 chance of winning $4.00, I ought to be willing to<br />

pay some money to play it. If I have to pay $0.50 each time I play, I will still come<br />

out ahead, even though I will lose the $0.50 on three out of every four plays.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!