02.03.2013 Views

Thinking and Deciding

Thinking and Deciding

Thinking and Deciding

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

412 MORAL JUDGMENT AND CHOICE<br />

Naturalism<br />

Naturalism is the bias toward nature. It is also related to omission bias, because<br />

“nature” often defines the default situation, the result of inaction, as in the case of<br />

the vaccination, where the disease can be assumed to be natural. (Of course, the<br />

result of omission is not always natural, as in the case of the dictator just described.)<br />

Chapter 20 presents evidence that people regard harms caused by people as worse<br />

than otherwise equivalent harms caused by nature. Spranca (1992) found that people<br />

would often pay extra to drink “natural water” rather than water that had been distilled<br />

<strong>and</strong> then had exactly the right chemicals added to it so that it was chemically<br />

identical to natural water. Baron, Holzman, <strong>and</strong> Schulkin (1998) found that many<br />

doctors would prefer to give “natural” hormones to menopausal women, rather than<br />

chemically identical synthetic hormones.<br />

Physical proximity<br />

People consider harm to be worse when it involves physical contact with the victim.<br />

For example, people regard it as worse to “push a man off of a footbridge <strong>and</strong> in front<br />

of a train in order to cause the man to fall <strong>and</strong> be hit by the train, thereby slowing<br />

it <strong>and</strong> saving five people ahead on the tracks” than to “pull a lever that redirects a<br />

trolley onto a side track in order to save five people ahead on the main track if, as a<br />

side-effect, pulling the lever drops a man off a footbridge <strong>and</strong> in front of the train on<br />

the side tracks, where he will be hit” (Cushman, Young, <strong>and</strong> Hauser, 2006).<br />

Other possible biases, already mentioned earlier in this chapter, include relativism,<br />

moral realism, <strong>and</strong> the existence of moralistic values <strong>and</strong> protected values.<br />

Let me emphasize again that the term “bias” here, as elsewhere in this book, is<br />

not pejorative. A finding of bias in judgment does not mean that the judge should be<br />

punished or condemned. It does mean that she should be educated if that is possible,<br />

<strong>and</strong> if we have sufficient confidence in our normative model. We must bear in mind<br />

that we can make both kinds of errors: miseducating someone who doesn’t really<br />

need it <strong>and</strong> failing to educate someone who does need it. In real prescriptive situations,<br />

you might want to take some small risk of miseducation errors. Note also that<br />

education here means persuasion not indoctrination. Without underst<strong>and</strong>ing, utilitarian<br />

moral principles are far less likely to be used correctly, <strong>and</strong> underst<strong>and</strong>ing can be<br />

achieved only by giving reasons.<br />

In sum, then, we have two different reasons for looking for nonutilitarian biases.<br />

First, from the perspective of psychological theory, utilitarianism serves as a kind of<br />

null hypothesis. Judgments that we should do the most good are easy to explain in<br />

many ways <strong>and</strong> do not enlighten us much about the psychology of moral judgment. If<br />

everyone said that only the amount of harm mattered <strong>and</strong> not whether it was indirect<br />

or direct, this would be easy to explain in terms of a general principle that moral<br />

intuitions are designed to prevent harm. If this were the only principle that people<br />

used, it could be explained in so many ways as to be uninformative.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!