02.03.2013 Views

Thinking and Deciding

Thinking and Deciding

Thinking and Deciding

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

MORALITY AND PRUDENCE 495<br />

Morality <strong>and</strong> prudence<br />

Parfit (1984) makes an interesting argument concerning the relation between concern<br />

about our future <strong>and</strong> concern about others. Does it make sense, Parfit asks, to care<br />

about your own future — the future “you” who is a different person from the present<br />

“you” — but not about someone else’s present? Is there a relevant difference? In<br />

either case, our concern goes beyond our own immediate welfare. Let us look at an<br />

example.<br />

Consider three people: Jill-1, Jill-2, <strong>and</strong> Jack. Now it just so happens that Jill-2<br />

is Jill-1 as she will be in the future, say ten years from now. Why should Jill-1 care<br />

more about Jill-2 than about Bill? Is it because Jill-2 will share memories with Jill-<br />

1? Probably not. Imagine that Jill-2 is amnesic (forgot her past), or that Jill-1 could<br />

transfer all of her memories to Bill. Would this change Jill-1’s reasons for caring<br />

about Jill-2?<br />

What about the fact that Jill-1 makes plans for Jill-2? Would this justify her<br />

caring about Jill-2? Again, this does not seem relevant. Jill-2 could change the plans<br />

that Jill-1 makes, or Jill-1 might neglect to make any, <strong>and</strong> it would not seem to matter.<br />

In fact, Parfit argues, it is difficult to think of any reason why anyone ought to care<br />

about herself in the distant future that does not also apply to caring about someone<br />

else in the present (or future), at least to some degree.<br />

The question “Why be moral?” occurs to many people, but the question “Why<br />

care about one’s own future?” occurs to few. By showing the similarity of these<br />

questions, Parfit suggests that it may not be any more difficult to care about other<br />

people than it is to care about our future selves.<br />

The virtues connected with caring about one’s own future are often called prudence,<br />

<strong>and</strong> prudential judgments are those concerned with one’s long-term interest<br />

(just as certain moral judgments are those involving the interests of others). Both<br />

prudence <strong>and</strong> morality require that we put aside immediate temptation for the sake<br />

of some distant good — our own future, or the interests of others. Therefore, selfcontrol<br />

is a virtue required for both morality <strong>and</strong> prudence.<br />

Moreover, prudent behavior <strong>and</strong> moral behavior usually reinforce one another<br />

(as most of our parents told us). If we are good to other people, if we respect their<br />

concerns <strong>and</strong> interests, if we keep our commitments to them, then we, in turn, will<br />

benefit in the future, for others will be obliged (usually) to treat us the same way.<br />

Similarly, concern for one’s own long-term future is likely to motivate certain behavior<br />

that turns out to benefit others. For example, the hard work required to become a<br />

physician pays off not only in terms of the respect <strong>and</strong> tangible rewards that physicians<br />

earn but also in terms of the good works that physicians accomplish on behalf<br />

of others: curing their illnesses.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!