02.03.2013 Views

Thinking and Deciding

Thinking and Deciding

Thinking and Deciding

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

400 MORAL JUDGMENT AND CHOICE<br />

must switch their utilities too.) Notice that when you do this, we are basically trying<br />

to maximize their combined utility, as if we were applying MAUT (Chapter 14),<br />

with each person providing one dimension of a decision involving two independent<br />

dimensions.<br />

Notice that the comparison is of differences or changes, not levels. All we need to<br />

decide is whether John’s playing his music increases his utility more than it decreases<br />

Judy’s. We do not need to decide whether John is happier or better off than Judy in<br />

general. Likewise, in considering a tax on the rich to help the poor, we should ask<br />

whether the decrease in utility for the rich is smaller than the increase for the poor.<br />

For making the relevant comparison, we need not consider absolute levels of utility.<br />

We are concerned only with the consequences of a particular decision, <strong>and</strong> we want to<br />

know whether the good that results from some option — compared to an alternative<br />

option — is greater than the harm.<br />

Comparisons of utility differences are difficult, but we do make them, on the<br />

basis of the same sort of information we use to think about tradeoffs within other<br />

individuals. It is clear, for example, that the utility that my friend Bill gains from<br />

having a $30 bottle of wine with his dinner out, instead of a $15 bottle, is less than<br />

the utility gain to someone else from having her malaria cured. (The comparison is<br />

even easier if the disease is fatal without the cure.) If I could purchase a cure for $15<br />

by making Bill forgo the more expensive wine, other things being equal, I ought to<br />

do it. Other comparisons are more difficult, but the difficulty of making them is only<br />

amatterofdegree.<br />

The fact that we make such comparisons does not necessarily make them meaningful.<br />

Comparisons of utilities across people could be like comparisons of the saltiness<br />

of colors. We can make such judgments, <strong>and</strong> we might even agree somewhat on<br />

them. But there is no truth about them.<br />

Can we imagine some kind of yardstick that would have the same utility for two<br />

people? That would be a starting point. Let us imagine two identical twins with<br />

identical experiences. 3 Suppose each twin is given a thirty-volt electric shock lasting<br />

for one minute. It is reasonable to assume that this has the same utility for both of<br />

them. Pure experiences of this sort could serve as the yardstick we are seeking. We<br />

have no reason to question the equivalence of the experience for both twins.<br />

We could extend this to cases of people less closely related. We know something<br />

about what makes people respond differently to painful experiences, <strong>and</strong> we could<br />

use this knowledge to make reasonable guesses about the utility of the same event<br />

for different people. The less similar the people are, the more error our judgment<br />

will have, but error is present in all judgments. The point is that we have reasons for<br />

our judgments of interpersonal comparison of utility. They are not like judging the<br />

saltiness of colors.<br />

Once we have the yardstick, we can use it to measure other goals, goals that do<br />

not involve experiences only. We could do this by asking for judgments within in-<br />

3 This is not truly possible, but it is approximately possible, <strong>and</strong> certainly imaginable, <strong>and</strong> this is all we<br />

need for a an argument about normative theory.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!