02.03.2013 Views

Thinking and Deciding

Thinking and Deciding

Thinking and Deciding

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

106 NORMATIVE THEORY OF PROBABILITY<br />

In sum, we can study numerical probabilities for three reasons. First, they can tell<br />

us about the rationality of belief — its conformity to a normative model — as long as<br />

we are careful not to assume that our subjects know how to assign numbers in a way<br />

that conforms to the normative model. Second, we can study people’s underst<strong>and</strong>ing<br />

of the normative model itself. Such an underst<strong>and</strong>ing can be useful to people who<br />

want to think carefully about the relationships among certain sets of their beliefs,<br />

such as physicians trying to diagnose a disease. Third, because probabilities are used<br />

to communicate belief strengths, we can study the accuracy of communication.<br />

What is probability?<br />

At the outset, one might ask whether probability judgments are really “judgments”<br />

at all. Aren’t they much more objective than that? Crapshooters who know that the<br />

probability of snake eyes is 1/36 are not making a judgment; they are using the result<br />

of a mathematical calculation. Surely the weather forecaster <strong>and</strong> the surgeon are<br />

doing something like that too — or are they? How do we tell whether a probability<br />

judgment is correct? Is there an objective st<strong>and</strong>ard?<br />

The question of what it means to say that a probability statement is “correct”<br />

has been the subject of competing theories, <strong>and</strong> the disagreement continues today.<br />

I would like to begin this discussion by doing some reflective thinking about three<br />

theories that bear on this issue (see Hacking, 1975; Savage, 1954; von Winterfeldt<br />

<strong>and</strong> Edwards, 1986).<br />

The question of when probability statements are correct has two subquestions:<br />

(1) How should we make or construct well-justified probability judgments? For<br />

example, when is a surgeon justified in saying that an operation has a .90 probability<br />

of success? (2) How should we evaluate such judgments after we know the truth of<br />

the matter? For example, how would we evaluate the surgeon’s probability judgment<br />

if the operation succeeds, or if it fails?<br />

These are not the same question. I may be well justified in saying that a substance<br />

is water if I have observed that the substance is odorless <strong>and</strong> colorless, with a boiling<br />

point of 212 degrees Fahrenheit <strong>and</strong> a freezing point of 32 degrees Fahrenheit. I<br />

would find that I had been wrong in hindsight, however, if the chemical formula of<br />

the substance turned out to be XYZ rather than H2O (Putnam, 1975). In the case of<br />

water, we accept the chemical formula as the ultimate criterion of correctness, the<br />

ultimate evaluation of statements about what is water <strong>and</strong> what is not. We would still<br />

consider people to be well justified if they judged the substance to be water on the<br />

basis of its properties alone, even if our evaluation later showed that their judgment<br />

had been incorrect.<br />

I shall discuss three theories. The first says that probability statements are about<br />

frequencies, the second says that they are about logical possibilities, <strong>and</strong> the third<br />

says that they are personal judgments. The frequency theory gives the same answer<br />

to the construction question as to the evaluation question, <strong>and</strong> so does the logical

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!