02.03.2013 Views

Thinking and Deciding

Thinking and Deciding

Thinking and Deciding

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

RISK REGULATION AND THE INTUITIONS THAT SUPPORT IT 505<br />

lated a ratio. The economic benefits are calculated either in terms of contributions<br />

to the average person’s income or in terms of how much the average person spends<br />

on it. The risks are the annual fatalities. Among the activities with high risk/benefit<br />

ratios were (when these studies were done) motorcycles, smoking, alcohol, hunting,<br />

swimming, <strong>and</strong> air travel (including private planes). For example, air travel (a typical<br />

member of this group) had (in 1979) about 1,000 fatalities in return for benefits<br />

of about $3,000,000,000 (Fischhoff, Lichtenstein, Slovic, Derby, <strong>and</strong> Keeney, 1981,<br />

p. 85). Among the activities with low risk/benefit ratios were commercial air travel,<br />

nuclear power, large construction, home appliance, <strong>and</strong> railroads, with an average<br />

benefit of about $30,000,000,000 for every 1,000 fatalities. These estimates are very<br />

loose, of course, <strong>and</strong> they vary from study to study (Fischhoff et al., 1981). But the<br />

point is clear, we spend more money regulating involuntary risks.<br />

In the psychometric study just described (Slovic et al., 1985), involuntary exposure,<br />

as judged by the subjects, was correlated with judged need for more stringent<br />

regulation, across risks. This seems at first to be a bias. We could save more lives by<br />

spending resources more equally on voluntary <strong>and</strong> involuntary risks.<br />

But, on closer examination, it is not clearly a bias. People may differ in the value<br />

(utility) they place on their lives or health, relative to the value the place on other<br />

things, such as the excitement of skiing or riding a motorcycle, the cool image of the<br />

smoker, or the social benefits <strong>and</strong> good feeling that comes from alcohol. If this is true<br />

to some extent, then — to that extent — people who suffer or die from these activities<br />

are just getting what they bargained for. They accepted the risk as part of the deal. At<br />

least some of these people made a rational decision to ride a motorcycle, go skiing, or<br />

drink. If the decision was rational for them, then any government attempt to prevent<br />

them from doing these things would be a harm. By contrast, nobody gets any thrill<br />

from the risk of exposure to air pollution or bacteria in the water. Thus, our relative<br />

lack of concern for voluntary risks might be rational.<br />

Of course, we might overdo it. Some of these activities affect others, if only<br />

because we could not bring ourselves to deny treatment <strong>and</strong>, if needed, lifetime care<br />

to someone who suffered brain damage from not wearing a motorcycle helmet, so<br />

we would end up paying for this. It is hard to tell, though, whether our concern with<br />

voluntary risk is too much, too little, or about right.<br />

Known versus unknown<br />

Recall that Factor 1 from the psychometric studies includes unknown risk. Most<br />

unknown risks are those of new technologies, such as new kinds of crops resulting<br />

from genetic engineering. In some studies, people think that risks should be more<br />

highly regulated when the level of the risk is unknown. This belief is related to the<br />

ambiguity effect discussed in Chapter 11. Ambiguity is the perception that missing<br />

information could change our probabilities. People tend to avoid ambiguous options.<br />

Attitudes toward risk regulation seem to be based on the idea that allowing the public<br />

to be exposed to an unknown risk is an option of this sort.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!