02.03.2013 Views

Thinking and Deciding

Thinking and Deciding

Thinking and Deciding

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

RANK-DEPENDENT UTILITY THEORIES 273<br />

Rectangular. Another because “it offers a majority of chances of at least an amount<br />

somewhere between $40 <strong>and</strong> $159. The odds of winning are best between these<br />

dollar amounts, <strong>and</strong> the odds indicate an excellent chance of winning an amount<br />

between $80 <strong>and</strong> $119.” Lopes (1996) notes that subjects tend to think in terms of<br />

the chances of getting a large amount, or a very low amount, or “at least as much<br />

as” some amount. The latter statement refers to an aspiration level, <strong>and</strong> the idea<br />

of “at least as much” implies that the subject is thinking about the sum of all the<br />

probabilities of that amount or larger.<br />

Lopes (1996) argues that a good approximation of risky decisions can be achieved<br />

by considering how people think about security, opportunity, <strong>and</strong> aspiration. Security<br />

is reflected in terms of the attention people pay to the worst outcome. Opportunity<br />

is reflected in attention to the best outcome, <strong>and</strong> aspiration is the attention<br />

they pay to whether a certain desired level is achieved. This is somewhat different<br />

from prospect theory, which roughly divides outcomes into those above <strong>and</strong> below<br />

the status quo.<br />

Lopes’s theory is a member of a broader class of theories called “rank dependent.”<br />

15 The idea is that people evaluate prospects (possible outcomes of choosing<br />

an option) in terms of their rank, such as best, second best, third best, ...worst.<br />

Rank dependence is usually combined with another idea, that people treat probabilities<br />

as cumulative. That is, when people evaluate prospects with several outcomes,<br />

they behave as if they thought of the probability of doing “at least as well as” some<br />

outcome (or, “no better than”). This contrasts with the view of prospect theory that<br />

people think of the probability of each individual outcome. People still apply a utility<br />

function to the outcomes one by one, as assumed by prospect theory.<br />

The difference between cumulative <strong>and</strong> non-cumulative models has to do with<br />

the way in which probabilities are transformed. The π function applies to individual<br />

probabilities. In cumulative rank-dependent theories, some other function applies to<br />

the cumulative probability, the probability of doing at least as well as some outcome.<br />

An example of such a function is shown in Figure 11.3 (adapted from Birnbaum <strong>and</strong><br />

Chavez, 1997). This figure applies to a gamble with four outcomes. P is the probability<br />

of doing at least as well as that outcome, <strong>and</strong> w(P ) is a weighing function that<br />

distorts P . W (P ) is like π(P ), but it applies to cumulative probability rather than<br />

to probability itself. The decision weight assigned to each outcome is the difference<br />

between W (P ) for that outcome <strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> W (P ) for the next higher outcome. (For<br />

the best outcome this difference is just W (Pbest), because the probability of doing<br />

better is zero. In Figure 11.3, the difference is represented with w.) For the function<br />

shown in Figure 11.3, the decision weight is highest for the worst outcome <strong>and</strong> next<br />

highest for the best outcome. A person with this function would be somewhat risk<br />

averse but would not pay much attention to outcomes other than the worst <strong>and</strong> the<br />

best.<br />

One property of this function is that the decision weights necessarily add to 1.<br />

This is not true of prospect theory in its original form. Strictly speaking, a person<br />

15 The first published theory of this type seems to be that of Quiggin (1982).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!