02.03.2013 Views

Thinking and Deciding

Thinking and Deciding

Thinking and Deciding

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

82 LOGIC<br />

For each system of logic, we can ask whether people actually make inferences<br />

in a way that is consistent with the rules of logic. When we do think logically, we<br />

can ask how we do it. It is not necessarily by following the rules as stated in logic<br />

textbooks. When we do not, we can ask why not <strong>and</strong> whether the problem can be<br />

corrected.<br />

For propositional logic, there is considerable evidence that people (at least adults)<br />

have learned to follow many rules that correspond directly to some of the major<br />

argument forms. For example, consider the following syllogisms (from Braine <strong>and</strong><br />

Rumain,1983, p. 278):<br />

1. There is a G. There is an S. Therefore there is a G <strong>and</strong> an S.<br />

2. There is an O <strong>and</strong> a Z. Therefore there is an O.<br />

3. There is a D or a T. There is not a D. Therefore there is a T.<br />

4. If there is a C or a P, there is an H. There is a C. Therefore there is an H.<br />

These inferences are so obvious (once we underst<strong>and</strong> the words) that no thinking<br />

seems to be required to evaluate their truth. Moreover, we seem to be able to<br />

draw more complex inferences by stringing these simple ones together. For example,<br />

evaluate the argument “If there is an A or a B, there is a C. There is a B or a<br />

D. There is not a D. Therefore there is a C.” This argument combines forms 3 <strong>and</strong> 4<br />

in the list. Braine <strong>and</strong> Rumain (1983) <strong>and</strong> Rips (1983) review <strong>and</strong> report a number<br />

of studies of such reasoning. It is possible to predict the difficulty of evaluating an<br />

argument by figuring out which of the basic arguments from propositional logic must<br />

be put together in order to make it up. This approach to the study of logic has been<br />

called natural logic or natural deduction. The name reflects the idea that certain<br />

forms of argument are just as easy for most of us to use <strong>and</strong> underst<strong>and</strong> as speaking.<br />

Researchers have been particularly interested in finding out how we have acquired<br />

these abilities. Studies of children suggest that some of them are slow to appear,<br />

developing only as children mature (Braine <strong>and</strong> Rumain, 1983).<br />

Difficulties in logical reasoning<br />

The natural-logic approach sometimes works for propositional logic, but it does not<br />

seem to work for categorical logic. First, categorical syllogisms seem to be much<br />

harder. Moreover, the difficulties are of a different sort. In most problems in propositional<br />

logic, we either see an answer right away or we puzzle over the problem,<br />

sometimes solving it, sometimes not. In categorical reasoning, we almost always<br />

come up with an answer, but the answer very often turns out to be wrong. Consider<br />

this very difficult example (from Johnson-Laird <strong>and</strong> Bara, 1984): Given the<br />

statements<br />

No A are B.<br />

All B are C.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!