02.03.2013 Views

Thinking and Deciding

Thinking and Deciding

Thinking and Deciding

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

108 NORMATIVE THEORY OF PROBABILITY<br />

weather-forecasting example. Most of us intuitively underst<strong>and</strong> what the forecaster<br />

is trying to do. A theory of probability that disallows this activity is a strange theory<br />

indeed, <strong>and</strong> once again we are compelled to look for alternatives. 2<br />

The logical theory<br />

The logical theory of probability is the theory usually assumed in most introductory<br />

treatments of probability, especially with respect to card games <strong>and</strong> dice. The<br />

theory is useful when we can define a set of logically equivalent, or exchangeable,<br />

propositions. The evidence for each of these propositions is the same, <strong>and</strong> any two<br />

of them can be exchanged without affecting our beliefs in their truth, so their probabilities<br />

must be the same. Typically, when we make calculations in card games,<br />

we regard every card remaining in a deck as equally likely to be drawn, because the<br />

only evidence we have for any particular card is simply that it is somewhere in the<br />

deck <strong>and</strong> we have exactly this evidence for each of the cards. The cards are logically<br />

equivalent.<br />

Suppose I flip three coins. We generally think of the three flips as exchangeable,<br />

because we think that the order does not matter, <strong>and</strong> we think that the names we give<br />

to the coins do not matter either. There are eight compound events (three-flip units)<br />

that can be made up of these basic, exchangeable propositions: HHH (heads, heads,<br />

heads), THH (tails, heads, heads), HTH, HHT, TTH, THT, HTT, <strong>and</strong> TTT. In half of<br />

these compound events, the first coin comes up heads; hence, the probability of this<br />

event is 1/2. In1/4 of these worlds, the first two coins come up heads; hence the<br />

probability of both of these events is 1/4, <strong>and</strong> so on. Of course, each of these events<br />

corresponds to an infinite set of atomic possible worlds.<br />

Like the frequency view, the logical view holds that probability is objective —<br />

that is, it is something that can be known. When two individuals give different probability<br />

judgments, at most one can be correct. As in logic, once the premises are<br />

accepted, the conclusion follows. The assumptions here concern exchangeability.<br />

An advantage of the logical view is that it solves the problem raised by the coin.<br />

It explains quite well why we believe that the probability of a coin’s coming up heads<br />

is 1/2.<br />

A disadvantage is that it is usually impossible to find exchangeable events. I<br />

cannot sensibly enumerate equally likely possibilities in order to calculate the probability<br />

of rain tomorrow, in the way that I would enumerate the possible poker h<strong>and</strong>s<br />

in order to calculate the probability of a flush. Therefore, like the frequency theory,<br />

the logical theory renders many everyday uses of probability nonsensical. When I<br />

want to evaluate my physician’s judgment of the probability that I have strep throat,<br />

it does not help to ask about the proportion of exchangeable events in which I would<br />

2 Another, more subtle, argument (from Hacking, 1965) against this view is that some sequences may<br />

have no limit. Consider the sequence HTTHHHTTTTTT .... Inthissequence,Hisfollowedbyenough<br />

Ts so that there are 2/3 Ts, then T is followed by enough Hs so that there are 2/3 Hs, <strong>and</strong> so on,<br />

alternating. If you were dropped into the middle of the sequence somewhere, it would be reasonable to<br />

think that your chance of l<strong>and</strong>ing on a T would be .5, yet this sequence has no limit.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!