02.03.2013 Views

Thinking and Deciding

Thinking and Deciding

Thinking and Deciding

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

CONCLUSION 255<br />

7. On the basis of your answers to questions 4 <strong>and</strong> 6, what is the relation between the curvature<br />

of the utility function <strong>and</strong> risk attitude (risk seeking versus risk averse), according to expectedutility<br />

theory?<br />

8. Assume that the utility of yearly income X is X .5 . If you have $50,000 in income to divide<br />

between two people, what division will maximize their total utility? Show your work. (You<br />

can do this graphically, if you do not know calculus.)<br />

Conclusion<br />

Utility theory as a normative model tells us what it means for a decision to be best<br />

for achieving our goals. The theory has been widely applied as the basis of decision<br />

analysis. It plays another important role, however, in justifying the prescriptive<br />

model of actively open-minded thinking. Actively open-minded thinking about decisions<br />

helps us to achieve our goals because it helps us to maximize utility. The<br />

expected utility of a neglected possibility (option) could be higher than that of any<br />

option that was considered, so we do well to search thoroughly for options. Likewise,<br />

neglecting a possible piece of evidence (possible consequence) or goal (attribute), or<br />

weighing the evidence in a biased way, could lead us to choose an option with less<br />

utility than the best option we could choose. Parallel arguments can be made for<br />

the importance of actively open-minded thinking in belief formation. Beliefs formed<br />

after a thorough search for evidence <strong>and</strong> an unbiased evaluation of that evidence are<br />

the most useful for decision making. They reflect the evidence available most accurately<br />

<strong>and</strong> correspond to better-calibrated probability judgments, so they help us to<br />

maximize utility in the long run.<br />

Utility theory also justifies my claim that thorough search is a virtue to be practiced<br />

in moderation. The utility of search is negative, <strong>and</strong> the compensating expected<br />

benefits decline as search continues: There is a point of diminishing returns in the<br />

expected utility of thinking itself.<br />

Utility theory in general can also serve as a prescriptive model for decision making,<br />

as well as a normative model. When we make real decisions, it may usually be<br />

helpful to ask ourselves what produces the best expected outcome. This heuristic —<br />

<strong>and</strong> it is a heuristic — may lead us to make decisions that produce good outcomes.<br />

In the next chapter we shall look at the descriptive theory of decision making.<br />

Departures from utility theory, we shall discover, provide further reasons not to trust<br />

decisions made without adequate thought or formal analysis.<br />

Answers to exercises<br />

1. The line plotted on the graph should pass through the origin <strong>and</strong> be curved downward.<br />

2. 0, √ 5, √ 10<br />

3. .5 · √ 10<br />

4. EU($5) is greater, thus showing risk aversion.<br />

5. These are the same. EV ($5) = $5.<br />

6. EU($5) = 25. EU($10,.5) = .5 · 100 = 50 > 25. This shows risk seeking when the utility<br />

function is convex.<br />

7. Concave implies risk aversion; convex implies risk seeking.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!