02.03.2013 Views

Thinking and Deciding

Thinking and Deciding

Thinking and Deciding

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

UTILITARIANISM AND FAIRNESS 421<br />

has been supported by many other experiments. If this is generally true, it makes us<br />

less concerned with victims of all sorts whom we feel we cannot help: victims of<br />

rape, of other crimes, of disease, of poverty, of having the wrong parents, of being<br />

born in the wrong country.<br />

In sum, people desire to see fairness. They will try to bring about fairness, even<br />

when utility is not maximized, <strong>and</strong> even when they must sacrifice to bring it about.<br />

When they cannot bring it about, they will try to deceive themselves into thinking<br />

that things are fair.<br />

Utilitarianism <strong>and</strong> fairness<br />

Equity theorists also maintain that people want rewards <strong>and</strong> punishments to be proportional<br />

to “inputs.” It is often unclear what the inputs are, though. Colleges in the<br />

United States typically allocate financial aid according to need, but graduate schools<br />

typically do not. Should need be an input? In assigning grades, should a teacher consider<br />

ability, effort, or just the end result? What is the input here? If some citizens<br />

contribute more than others, why should each citizen have one vote? Why doesn’t<br />

each stockholder have only one vote? Is the size of an investment an input? Should<br />

criminal penalties depend only on the magnitude of the crime? If so, are we wrong<br />

to excuse people who are insane?<br />

I suggest that it is useful here, as elsewhere, for us to consider the normative<br />

theory — to ask ourselves, “Just what is the ultimate goal we are trying to achieve?,”<br />

before we ask about people’s actual judgments. We may want to consider prescriptive<br />

theory as well. Although the philosophical accounts of fairness are rich <strong>and</strong> varied<br />

(for example, Nozick, 1974; Rawls, 1971), I shall concentrate here on the utilitarian<br />

account (Baron, 1993b, 1996), mentioning in passing where other accounts disagree<br />

with it.<br />

Utilitarians have both a simple answer <strong>and</strong> a complex answer to the problem of<br />

fairness. The simple answer is that we should strive to maximize utility. When asked<br />

how to do that, another simple answer is that it depends on the details of the case<br />

at h<strong>and</strong>. This is not very helpful guidance. The more complex answer is to present<br />

several principles that need to be considered. Let us look at some of these.<br />

Declining marginal utility. If you are asked to distribute $1,000 between two<br />

anonymous people, neither of whom you would ever see again, what would you do?<br />

Most people would divide the money equally. According to utilitarianism, this is<br />

normatively correct if we assume that the utility of money is marginally declining<br />

(Chapter 10). If two people have the same marginally declining utility function for<br />

money, <strong>and</strong> if we consider changing away from a fifty-fifty split, the utility benefits<br />

for one person that result from having a greater share will be more than outweighed<br />

by the utility of the losses for the other person.<br />

Even if the two people have different utility functions, equal division is still the<br />

best solution, as long as we do not know which utility function is which, <strong>and</strong> as<br />

long as both are marginally declining. We would want to make the division in order

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!