02.03.2013 Views

Thinking and Deciding

Thinking and Deciding

Thinking and Deciding

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

430 FAIRNESS AND JUSTICE<br />

great deal (if they sue), even when little deterrence results because the compensation<br />

is paid by liability insurance.<br />

Punishment. People often ignore deterrence in making decisions about punishment<br />

or penalties. Baron <strong>and</strong> Ritov (1993) gave a questionnaire to retired judges,<br />

law students, other students <strong>and</strong> other groups. The questionnaire asked respondents<br />

to imagine that the United States had a legal system (much like New Zeal<strong>and</strong>’s), in<br />

which separate decisions were made about penalties against injurers <strong>and</strong> compensation<br />

for victims (Baron <strong>and</strong> Ritov, 1993). In one case, a child died from a vaccine<br />

against a disease. The disease is far more likely than the vaccine to kill the child, <strong>and</strong><br />

the company was not clearly negligent. The case had two versions. In one version,<br />

“The company knew how to make an even safer pill but had decided against producing<br />

it because the company was not sure that the safer pill would be profitable. If<br />

the company were to stop making the pill that the woman took, it would make the<br />

safer pill.” In the other version, “If the company were to stop making the pill that<br />

the woman took, it would cease making pills altogether.” Of course, the deterrent<br />

effect of the penalty in this case would be the reverse of its usual effect, because it<br />

would provide an incentive for undesirable behavior rather than more desirable behavior.<br />

Most of the respondents, including judges, did not think that this made any<br />

difference. They thought that the penalty should depend on the harm done, not on<br />

its effect on anyone’s future behavior. For example, some subjects argued, “We are<br />

dealing with solely what happened to the woman.” “The damage was already done<br />

to that woman.” “It should have to pay damages if it was at fault.” “[The company]<br />

should pay for its previous actions on account of those actions.”<br />

In another test of the same principle, subjects assigned penalties to the company<br />

even when the penalty was secret, the company was insured, <strong>and</strong> the company was<br />

going out of business, so that (subjects were told) the amount of the penalty would<br />

have no effect on anyone’s future behavior. Such a situation would remove the usual<br />

deterrent effect of penalties. Baron, Gowda, <strong>and</strong> Kunreuther (1993) likewise found<br />

that subjects, including judges <strong>and</strong> legislators, typically did not want to penalize<br />

companies differently for dumping of hazardous waste as a function of whether the<br />

penalty would make companies try harder to avoid waste or whether it would induce<br />

them to cease making a beneficial product. Some writers have suggested that<br />

companies have in fact stopped making certain beneficial products, such as vaccines,<br />

exactly because of such penalties (for example, Inglehart, 1987).<br />

Subjects who want injurers to be punished even when the punishment has no<br />

benefit could be applying a rule of retribution, a rule that prescribes punishment as<br />

a function of the cause of the harm rather than the effect of the punishment. Such<br />

a rule normally yields the same result as does the utilitarian deterrence principle:<br />

Punishment for causing harm usually deters. In these cases, retribution does not<br />

deter. Because the retribution rule <strong>and</strong> the deterrence rule normally agree, it may be<br />

difficult for people who adopt the retribution rule ever to learn about its problems.<br />

Other possible sources of a retribution rule may be a perception of balance or equity<br />

(Walster, Walster, <strong>and</strong> Berscheid, 1978) <strong>and</strong> a generalization from the emotional<br />

response of anger, which may operate in terms of retribution.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!