02.03.2013 Views

Thinking and Deciding

Thinking and Deciding

Thinking and Deciding

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

CONCLUSION 287<br />

imperfect correlations” (Table 2.1). Prescriptively, we would do well to learn to<br />

distinguish the different kinds of cases. (In the case of ambiguity, I argued that what<br />

matters is whether it is worthwhile to wait until we can obtain the information we<br />

see as missing.) If we thought more about the heuristics that govern our decisions,<br />

we might be able to learn when these heuristics are helpful shortcuts <strong>and</strong> when they<br />

are self-made blinders that prevent us from achieving our goals.<br />

The violations of utility theory discussed in this chapter indicate clearly that the<br />

options we choose are often not the ones that best achieve our goals in the long run.<br />

Decision utility — the inference from our choices about what we value — does not<br />

match true (experienced) utility. In view of these findings, we can no longer assume<br />

— as many economists do — that we always know what is best for us <strong>and</strong> express this<br />

knowledge in our choices. The question of how we should deal with these violations<br />

is not fully solved. I have suggested that actively open-minded thinking <strong>and</strong> the<br />

judicious use of formal decision analysis (discussed in later chapters) are parts of the<br />

answer to this question, but we may also need to learn new heuristics specifically for<br />

making decisions.<br />

Answers to selected exercises:<br />

2. V (30) = 30 .5 =5.48<br />

v(45,.8) = π(.8) · v(45) = .65 · 45 .5 =4.36<br />

v(30,.25) = π(.25) · v(30) = .2375 · 30 .5 =1.30<br />

v(45,.2) = π(.2) · v(45) = .20 · 45 .5 =1.34<br />

3. u(30) = 30 .5 =5.48<br />

u(45,.8) = .8 · u(45) = .8 · 45 .5 =5.37<br />

u(30,.25) = .25 · u(30) = .25 · 30 .5 =1.37<br />

u(45,.2) = .20 · u(45) = .20 · 45 .5 =1.34<br />

Prospect theory overweighs p =1but otherwise underweighs differences in probabilities, such as the<br />

difference between .25 <strong>and</strong> .20. Hence the reversal of the ordering of the third <strong>and</strong> fourth gambles,<br />

according to the two theories. Utility theory must order the second pair of gambles by analogy with the<br />

first pair.<br />

4. All values are negative <strong>and</strong> twice those in question 2. The ordering of the gambles is reversed, because<br />

the preferred gamble is the one that is less negative. This is the “reflection effect.”<br />

5. v(X) =π(.5) · v($10)<br />

X .5 = .425 · $10 .5<br />

X = .4252 · $10 = $1.81<br />

u(X) =.5 · u($10)<br />

X .5 = .5 · $10 .5<br />

X = .52 · $10 = $2.50<br />

Prospect theory makes people seem more risk averse here because of the π function, which changes the<br />

.5 into .425. If gambles were used to measure the utility of money, the obtained function would be too<br />

concave.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!