02.03.2013 Views

Thinking and Deciding

Thinking and Deciding

Thinking and Deciding

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

INTUITIONS 433<br />

Subjects may (again) be extending an intuitive principle about equity to cases in<br />

which it has no justification. 4<br />

Preferences for ex-ante equity can have a cost. Suppose I have two nephews. I<br />

can give ten lottery tickets to one nephew or one ticket to each nephew. To get envy<br />

out of the picture while they are waiting for the results, suppose that they will never<br />

know that I have given them the tickets, <strong>and</strong> that, if one of them wins, he will simply<br />

be told that some unknown person gave him the winning ticket. Many people might<br />

still think that it is wrong to give more tickets to one nephew, because ex-ante equity<br />

is important in its own right, even though ex-post equity is impossible here. In the<br />

end, though, only one nephew can win, <strong>and</strong> giving one of them ten tickets makes<br />

such an event more likely. The expected achievement of my nephew’s goals — <strong>and</strong><br />

mine, insofar as I care about theirs — is greater with the unequal division. If I were<br />

to choose one ticket for each, I must deprive one nephew of an additional chance to<br />

win, <strong>and</strong> I could not justify this by saying that I had given the other a compensating<br />

gain.<br />

Chances to win are not the same as winnings. An equal-division rule for winnings<br />

is justified by the declining marginal utility of winnings themselves. But the utility<br />

of chances to win is not marginally declining. People may nevertheless apply the<br />

equal-division rule, because they do not know its justification. The same issue may<br />

arise in policy disputes concerning the distribution of risk, such as risk of illness from<br />

pollution. The simple utilitarian approach says that we should minimize overall risk.<br />

We should not be so concerned with equity.<br />

“Do no harm.” Baron <strong>and</strong> Jurney (1993), asked subjects if they would vote for<br />

various reforms. In one experiment, 39% of the subjects said they would vote for a<br />

100% tax on gasoline (to reduce global warming). Of those who would vote against<br />

the tax, 48% thought that it would do more good than harm on the whole. They were<br />

therefore not using a maximization principle. Of those subjects who would vote<br />

against the tax, despite judging that it would do more good than harm, 85% cited<br />

the unfairness of the tax as a reason for voting against it (for instance, the burden<br />

would fall more heavily on people who drive a lot), <strong>and</strong> 75% cited the fact that the<br />

tax would harm some people on the whole (for instance, drivers). These subjects are<br />

apparently unwilling to harm some people — relative to the status quo or relative<br />

to an ideal of fairness — in order to help others, even when they see the benefit as<br />

greater than the harm (Baron, 1993c, presents further evidence). This effect may be<br />

related to the “omission bias” discussed in Chapter 16.<br />

The perception of harm can be manipulated by framing. Kahneman, Knetsch,<br />

<strong>and</strong> Thaler, (1986b) told subjects, “A company is making a small profit. It is located<br />

in a community experiencing a recession with substantial unemployment but<br />

no inflation. There are many workers anxious to work at the company. The company<br />

decides to decrease wages <strong>and</strong> salaries 7% this year.” Most subjects (62%) thought<br />

4 A more complex utilitarian justification would say that Option 2, in the scenario with two people <strong>and</strong><br />

a coin flip, leaves both people with some hope, or, in Option 3, one person cannot grieve for the other. We<br />

could modify the situation to remove these justifications. We could say that the people do not know each<br />

other, <strong>and</strong> that they do not know of their risk. This would probably not change people’s judgments.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!