02.03.2013 Views

Thinking and Deciding

Thinking and Deciding

Thinking and Deciding

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

236 NORMATIVE THEORY OF CHOICE UNDER UNCERTAINTY<br />

Utility theory began in the seventeenth century, <strong>and</strong> its modern form began in<br />

1738 (Bernoulli, 1954). Its development since that time was largely associated with<br />

economic theory, where it became part of the descriptive theory of the behavior of<br />

buyers <strong>and</strong> sellers in markets. Psychologists became interested in utility theory in the<br />

early 1950s, soon after the publication of von Neumann <strong>and</strong> Morgenstern’s (1947)<br />

Theory of Games <strong>and</strong> Economic Behavior. 2 In 1953, the economist Maurice Allais<br />

argued that expected-utility theory fails as a descriptive model of decision making.<br />

Allais — <strong>and</strong> many others to follow — also questioned the normative status of<br />

the theory. Many scholars (especially economists, but also some psychologists <strong>and</strong><br />

philosophers) have been reluctant to admit that people sometimes behave irrationally<br />

or that our intuitive judgments can be misleading, so they have tried to develop criteria<br />

of rationality that are consistent with our behavior or our intuitions.<br />

The years since 1953 have seen constant tension between the attackers <strong>and</strong> defenders<br />

of expected-utility theory as normative. Both camps have engaged in efforts<br />

to develop better descriptive models of decision making. The attackers, who assume<br />

that people are generally rational, argue that better descriptive models will lead to<br />

better normative models. The defenders, who acknowledge the existence of irrational<br />

decision making, argue that the descriptive models will tell us where we fall<br />

short according to the normative model <strong>and</strong> will allow us to ask what, if anything,<br />

we can do about it. I take the view that our decisions are often irrational, <strong>and</strong> I shall<br />

defend utility theory as a normative model. I shall also point out, however, that there<br />

is room for various interpretations of utility theory as a normative model. The best<br />

interpretation of utility theory is still an open question even for those who believe, as<br />

I do, that the theory is essentially correct <strong>and</strong> that the descriptive violations of it are<br />

biases. The problems are what to count as “utility.”<br />

Utility is a number, but numbers have different roles. Is utility part of nature, in<br />

the way that mass <strong>and</strong> acceleration are? Is it something we discover? Or is more<br />

like something we make up, like the number of points in gin rummy? I think it<br />

is in between. It is a tool that is useful in thinking about decision making, but it is<br />

fundamentally an invention. In this regard, it is more like longitude, or time, than like<br />

mass <strong>and</strong> acceleration. Longitude is a useful concept that we impose on the earth. We<br />

could analyze our position differently, but any other way would be translatable into<br />

this way. The earth did not come with lines on it. Utility is like longitude in another<br />

way. The zero point is arbitrary. (We chose the Royal Observatory in Greenwich,<br />

Engl<strong>and</strong>.) And the units are arbitrary. We could have 360 degrees or 3, but once we<br />

choose the zero point <strong>and</strong> the units, we have no more freedom.<br />

The same is true of time. The calendar we use has an arbitrary zero point based<br />

on the supposed birth year of Jesus Christ. Units like years, hours, <strong>and</strong> seconds on,<br />

are also arbitrary (<strong>and</strong> do not work all that well together). The idea that we can<br />

add, subtract, <strong>and</strong> multiply measures of time in a useful way is a consequence of a<br />

mathematical model that we impose on the world, in which we conceive of time as<br />

a continuum that can be described by real numbers. It leads to new ways of thinking<br />

2 Edwards <strong>and</strong> Tversky (1967) reprint some important papers from this period.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!